Paul Ekman_Why Do Not We Catch Liars

Paul Ekman_Why Do Not We Catch Liars
Paul Ekman_Why Do Not We Catch Liars

Social Research, Vol. 63, No. 3, 801-817 (Fall 1996)

Paul Ekman’s research is supported by a Research Scientist Award from

the National Institute of Mental Health (MH06092).

Why Don’t We Catch Liars?

Paul Ekman

Our research (Ekman and O’Sullivan, 1990; Frank and Ekman, forthcoming; Ekman, Frank, and O’Sullivan, forthcoming) suggests that most people cannot tell from demeanor whether someone is lying or telling the truth. Such poor performance is not because lies are told flawlessly. Most liars make mistakes which could be detected but usually are missed. Both perpetrating a lie and detecting a lie, in most people, seem to be poorly developed skills. In this article, I consider six explanations for why most of us do not catch liars from demeanor. I will first explain how I distinguish lying from other forms of deceit, and then discuss the evidence which suggests that people are such poor lie catchers.

The intent of the liar is one of the two criteria I (Ekman, [1985] 1992) use to distinguish lies from other kinds of deception. The liar deliberately chooses to mislead the target. Liars may actually tell the truth, but that is not their intent. And truthful people may provide false information—bad advice from a stock broker—but that is not their intent. The~ liar has a choice; the liar could chose not to lie. We are all tempted to lie, but we do not always do so. Lying is not irresistible; it is, by my definition, a conscious, considered choice. I do recognize that lying can become a habit and then performed with little consideration, but, at least initially, all such habits began as considered choices about whether or not to do so. Presumably, a pathological liar is compelled to lie and by my definition, therefore, is not a liar.

The second criterion for distinguishing lies from other deceptions is that the target is not notified about the liar’s intention to mislead. A magician is not a liar by this criterion, but Uri Geller is a liar, since Geller claimed his tricks were not magic. An actor is not a liar, but an impostor is. Let the buyer beware is one example of an explicit warning that products or services may not be what they are presented to be. (Of course, that warning does not appear in advertisements, nearly all of which are designed to convey the opposite message.) Poker is still another situation in which the rules of the game sanction and notify the players that deception will occur, and, therefore, one cannot consider bluffing to be a lie.

Sometimes notification of an intention to mislead is implicit in the framing, to use Goffman’s (1974) term, of the situation. In real estate transactions, the potential buyer is implicitly notified that the seller’s asking price is not the actual price the seller would accept. Various forms of politeness are other instances in which the nature of the situation notifies the target that the truth may not be spoken. The host would not properly’ scrutinize the dinner guest to determine if the guest’s claim to have enjoyed the evening is true anymore than the aunt should worry whether the nephew is lying when he says that he appreciated being given a tie for Christmas. Deception is expected; even if the target might suspect that the truth is not being told, it is improper to question it. Only certain types of deception may be allowable: the poker player cannot use marked cards; the home seller cannot conceal a known defect.

In courtship, it is ambiguous whether the parties should expect truthfulness. The saying “all’s fair in love and war” would seem to warn lovers not to believe all they are told. Recent public opinion polls suggest that lies that downplay the number of previous sexual partners are common among college-aged adults. Yet I expect that lovers want to believe in the truthfulness of their lover. Many popular songs testify to the betrayal felt when lies are discovered (although some do warn that lies may be expected). Romantic love requires collusive efforts to develop and maintain myths about each other and the nature of the relationship.

I differ from Bok (1982), who only considers false statements to be lies. I (Ekman, [1985] 1992) argued that one can falsify without words, and one need not falsify, verbally or nonverbally, to lie. Concealment is just as much a lie as falsification, if there is an expectation that information will be revealed. When filling out a job application that asks for a listing of all previous employment, omitting the one from which one was fired would be a concealment lie, for there is an obligation to reveal. In personal relationships it is not always so clear cut, and the liar, once discovered, and the target of the lie may disagree about whether or not an obligation to reveal the concealed information was in force.

Concealment and falsification are different techniques for accomplishing the same objective. The issue is the motive, not the technique employed to accomplish it. If the motive is to mislead, then the choice between falsifying or concealing is simply a matter of which technique will work better in a given instance. Elsewhere (Ekman, [198531992) I have explained why most liars would prefer to conceal rather than falsify if the situation will allow it and also described some other techniques for implementing a lie.

Now let us consider what we know about how well people can detect lies from demeanor. The evidence that most people do poorly in catching lies comes from the following type of experiment. Students are recruited to lie or tell the truth about something which usually does not matter much to them. It has no relevance to their past or their expected future life. Sometimes in a weak (in my judgment) attempt to motivate them, they are told it is important to be able to lie, or that smart or successful people succeed in this task. Videotapes of their behavior are shown to other students who are asked to identify who is lying and who is telling the truth. Typically, most of those trying to catch the liars perform at chance or just slightly better than chance. Our (Ekman and Friesen, 1974; Ekman, Frank, and O’Sullivan, forthcoming) research has differed in a number of ways.

We have tried to make the lies relevant to their lives and to set the stakes for success or failure as high as we could. We attempted this for two reasons. It is only in high stake lies that emotions about lying (fear, guilt, excitement, or what I have called duping delight) are likely to be aroused and betray the lie. It is not just the leakage of these strong emotions which provide behavioral clues to deceit, but these strong emotions also max’ disruPt the liar’s cognitive processing and result in evasive, implausible, and stumbling accounts. A second reason for studying high stake lies is that these are the lies with which society is most concerned.

In one of our experimental scenarios, we examined how well nurses could conceal the negative emotions they felt when witnessing films showing amputations and burns. They were

highly motivated to succeed in this lie, because they thought our experiment offered them the opportunity to develop a skill they would need to use when confronting just such upsetting scenes in their future work. In another of our scenarios, the subjects had a chance to take and keep $50 if they could convince the interrogator they’ had not taken the money. Those subjects who did not take the money could earn $10 if the interrogator believed them when they’ said they had not taken the $50. In our last scenario, we first identified the social issues the subjects felt most strongly about, and then asked them to describe that opinion honestly (and earn $10 if believed) or claim to have the opposite of their true opinion (and earn $50 if believed).

In our most recent work we gave some of our subjects the choice as to whether to lie or tell the truth, as people have in real life. There are many reasons why some people choose not to lie, one of which is their own knowledge, based on past experience, that they are almost always caught. Including in the sample of liars such terrible liars, people who would not choose to lie unless forced to do so by the experimenter, could inflate the detection rate. In virtually all previous research, on either interpersonal deception or polygraph lie detection, subjects were not given the choice as to whether to lie or be truthful. One exception is the study of the polygraph by Ginton, Daie, Elaad, and Ben-Shakhar (1982), in which they were able to know which policemen had cheated on a test for eligibility for promotion; Stiff, Corman, Knizek, and Snider (1994) in a similar fashion knew which students cheated on a quiz. Bradley (1988) also allowed subjects to choose whether to lie or tell the truth in a polygraph study.

Another unique feature of our recent experiments is that we told the subjects that they would be punished, and it was a considerable punishment, if the interrogator judged them to be lying. Both the truthful person mistakenly judged to be lying and the liar who was detected would receive the same punishment. Thus, for the first time in research on lying, both the truthful person and the liar might be afraid—of being disbelieved if telling the truth, of being caught if lying. If it is only the liar who might be afraid of being accused of lying, it is too easy’ for the lie catcher and not relevant to most of real life. And if neither liar nor the truthful person fear punishment, it should have little relevance to the lies that occur in the criminal justice world or in national security, let alone in marital disputes, parent-child conflicts, and so on.

Although our recent experiments can claim to have more ecological validity than our older studies, or than most of the literature on either interpersonal deceit or polygraph lie detection, the findings about detectability were not much different. Most of those who saw the videotapes and made their judgments operated at a chance level or only slightly better than chance. Before proceeding to consider why people do so poorly as lie-catchers, let us consider some limitations of our research which could have led us to underestimate the ability to detect lies from demeanor.

For the most part, the observers who judged who was lying and who was telling the truth had no vital interest at stake in achieving accuracy. They were not offered higher pay if they were more accurate. And catching liars was not intrinsically rewarding, for most of these people did not make a living catching liars. This limitation was addressed in our (Ekman and

O’Sullivan, 1991) study and work by other research groups (Kraut and Poe, 1980; DePaulo and Pfeifer, 1986) which did study professionals concerned with catching liars. We found that customs officials, policemen, trial court judges, F.B.I., C.I.A., B.A.T.F., D.E.A., forensic

psychiatrists, and trial lawyers were not much better than chance.

Perhaps accuracy would be higher if those making the judgments had been able to ask the questions, rather than being passive observers. I cannot rule this out, although I doubt it would be so. The requirement to formulate questions might well detract from the ability to process the information provided by the person being judged. It is for this reason that in many interrogations one person asks the questions while another sits passively considering the suspects responses. It would be interesting to have professional interrogators ask the questions in our experiments and then determine if those who see the videotapes generated were more accurate than has been so far found.

Our observers were not familiar with those whom they judged, and it might be argued that such familiarity would benefit accuracy. There are, of course, many situations in which judgments about lying are made without any prior familiarity with the person being evaluated, and our experiments at least are relevant to those instances. But I doubt that familiarity always benefits lie detection. While it should provide the basis for discounting idiosyncratic behaviors, it may do so at a cost. We tend to become invested in our friendships and work relationships, and the wish to preserve them may lead us to develop blindness to behaviors which could disrupt them. Trust makes one vulnerable to being misled, as usual levels of wariness are reduced and the benefit of the doubt is routinely given.

Involvement in a relationship can lead also to confidence in one’s ability to detect deception (Sillars and Scott, 1983), and such confidence may itself make one more vulnerable (Levine and McCornack, 1992). Familiarity should be an unmitigated benefit only when it is with a person one has had reason to distrust, and about whom one has acquired knowledge of how and when they betray the relationship.

In our experiments, the observers were only shown a few minutes of each interview before being required to make their judgment. But longer samples may not necessarily benefit lie detec-tion. We did do one study in which the samples shown were twice as long, and accuracy did not improve. Furthermore, we know from the behavioral measurements we have done that there are clues to deceit in these shorter samples. Nevertheless, we cannot rule out this limitation. If people were given much longer samples to judge, of an hour or two, accuracy might improve.

A critic might also have wondered if accuracy was so poor because there were few behavioral clues to deceit, but, as I have just mentioned, that is not the case in our experiments. Measurements we and our collaborators have done of the facial movements, voice, and speech show that high levels of accuracy are possible—over 80 percent correct classifications of who is lying and who is telling the truth. While those measurements required slowed motion replays, we also know that accurate judgments are possible just by viewing the videotapes at real time. A small percent of those we have studied have reached 80 percent or better accuracy, and they have done so in judging more than one scenario, so it is unlikely their accuracy was a fluke. And we have found a few occupational groups which as a group were highly accurate. The United States Secret Service were highly accurate on the emotion lie; none of them scored at or below chance, and a third were above 80 percent accurate. Interrogators specially selected for their known skills and given a week of training showed similar accuracy on the opinion lie.

Although the stakes in the lies we studied were much higher than in other research on lying,

certainly they were not as high as they are in many criminal or national security cases. Perhaps if the stakes were much higher, the videotapes would have contained many obvious signs of deceit, resulting in much higher accuracy. I cannot argue against that possibility but, as I just described, there were some occupational groups who were accurate when judging our videotapes. The question remains why were all these other groups not accurate.

The information is there, and it can be detected by some but not by most. Before considering why the overwhelming majority of people do poorly, consider one more feature of our experiments which probably benefited accuracy and may have led us to over- rather than under-estimate accuracy. In all of our recent studies we have told our observers that between 40 and 60 percent of the people they will see are lying. Initially we did not give this instruction, and found that a group of policemen judged everyone they saw on the videotape as lying, later explaining that everyone lies, especially to the police. Knowing the base rate of lies is an advantage people do not always have, and should enhance lie detection. I have more to say about this later.

Granting that our evidence is not conclusive, nevertheless, our videotapes do contain behavioral clues to deceit, which some people can recognize accurately but most do not. For the purpose of this discussion, let us consider this evidence as suggesting that in actual life most people, the overwhelming majority of people, do not detect high stake lies from demeanor. The question I pose is why not, why can we not all do better at this? It is not that we do not care. Public opinion polls time and again show that honesty is among the top five characteristics people want in a leader, friend, or lover. And the world of entertainment is full of stories, films, and songs which describe the tragic consequences of betrayal.

My first explanation of why we may be such poor lie catchers is that we are not prepared by our evolutionary history to be either very good lie catchers or lie perpetrators.1 I suspect that

our ancestral environment was not one in which there were many opportunities to lie and get away with it, and the costs for being caught in a lie might have been severe. If this speculation is correct, there would not have been any selection for those people who were unusually adept in catching or perpetrating lies. The fossil record does not tell us much about social life, so one must speculate about what life as hunter-gatherers might have been like. I add to that my experience thirty years ago working in what was then a stone-age preliterate culture in what is now called Papua New Guinea.

There were no rooms with doors, little privacy in this group living, small village, in which everyone knew and saw everyone else every day. Lies would most often be betrayed by the target or someone else observing actions which contradicted the lie or by other physical evidence. Adultery was an activity which lying often attempted to conceal in the village where I lived. Such lies were uncovered not by reading the betrayer’s demeanor when proclaiming fidelity, but by stumbling over him or her in the bush.

Perhaps lies about beliefs, emotions, and plans could have better avoided detection in such an environment.2 But some of those lies would eventually lead to one or another action, and then my argument about how hard it is to conceal or falsify actions in a setting in which there is no privacy would apply.

In a society in which an individual’s survival depended on cooperative efforts with other

members of their village, the reputational loss for being caught in a high stake lie might well be deadly. No one might cooperate with someone known to have engaged in serious lies. One could not change spouses, jobs, or villages with any ease.

Cheney and Seyfarth (1990), in their chapter on animal deception, make very similar points. An important constraint against lying

. . . arises from a species social structure. Animals that live in stable social groups face special

problems in any attempt at deceptive communication. . . . Among socially living animals deceptive signals will probably have to be more subtle and occur at lower frequencies if they are to go

undetected. Equally important, if animals live in social groups in which some degree of cooperation is essential for survival, the need for cooperation can reduce the rate at which unreliable signals are given (1990, p. 189).

To have had some special skill in detecting (or perpetrating for that matter) lies would not have had much adaptive value in such circumstances. Serious, high stake lies probably did not occur that often because of limited opportunity and high costs. When lies were suspected or uncovered, it was probably not by judgments of demeanor. (Note I have focused just on intra-group lies; certainly lies might between groups, and their costs and detection could be quite different).3

While there are altruistic lies, my discussion has dealt with less friendly lies, lies that occur when one person gains an advantage, often at the cost of the target of the lie. When the advantage is gained by violating a rule or expectation, we call that cheating. Lies sometimes may be required to accomplish the cheating activity, and lies are always required to conceal having cheated. Those cheated do not typically appreciate being cheated and are motivated to uncover any lies involved. But cheating is not likely to have occurred often enough in our ancestral environment to confer some advantage on those who might have been unusually adept at spotting when it did occur. And as I argued earlier, there was probably so little privacy that cheats would be caught by means other than discerning their misdeeds from their demeanor. The biologist Alan Grafen wrote:

The incidence of cheating must be low enough that signaling remains on average honest. As

signalers maximize their fitness, this implies that the occasions on which cheating is

advantageous must be limited. Perhaps the signalers for whom cheating is advantageous are in a

minority, or that only on a minority of occasions does it pay a signaler to cheat. . . . Cheating is

expected in evolutionarily stable signal systems, but the system can be stable only if there is some reason why on most occasions cheating does not pay. Cheats impose a kind of tax on the meaning of the signal. The central fact about stable signaling systems is honesty, and the debasement of

the meaning of the signal by cheats must be limited if stability is to be maintained (1990, p. 533).

By this reasoning, signals that cheat, which I would call lies, should have a low incidence. Cosmides and Tooby’s (1992) findings suggest that we have evolved a sensitivity to rule infractions and do not reward cheaters, and this may explain why cheating does not occur often. However, our findings suggest that we are not likely to catch cheaters based on our ability to spot their lies from their demeanor but by other means.

To summarize my argument, our ancestral environment did not prepare us to be astute lie catchers. Those who might have been most adept in identifying a liar from demeanor would have had minimal advantage in the circumstances in which our ancestors probably lived. Serious lies probably did not occur often, because a lack of privacy would have made the chances of being caught high. Such a lack of privacy would also mean that lies would typically be discovered by direct observation or other physical evidence, rather than having to rely upon judgments of demeanor. Finally, in a cooperative, closed, small society, when lies are uncovered the reputational costs to the individual would be high and inescapable.

In modern industrial societies, the situation is nearly the reverse. The opportunities for lying are plentiful; privacy is easy to achieve, there are many closed doors. When caught, the social consequences need not be disastrous, for one can change jobs, change spouses, change villages.

A damaged reputation need not follow you. By this reasoning we live now in circumstances which encourage rather than discourage lying, when evidence and activity are more easily concealed and the need to rely upon demeanor to make our judgments would be greater. And we have not been prepared by our evolutionary history to be very sensitive to the behavioral clues relevant to lying.

If we grant that our evolutionary history did not prepare us to detect lies from demeanor, why do we not learn how to do so in the course of growing up? One possibility is that our parents teach us not to identify their lies. Their privacy may often require that they mislead their children about just what they are doing, when they are doing it, and why they are doing it.While sexual activity is one obvious focus of such lies, there might well be other activities which parents want to conceal from their children.4

A third explanation is that we generally prefer not to catch liars, because a trusting rather than a suspicious stance enriches life, despite the possible costs. To always doubt, to make false accusations, is not only unpleasant for the doubter, but undermines much chance of establishing intimacy in mating, friendships, or on-going work relationships. We cannot afford to disbelieve a friend, our child, or our spouse when they are actually telling the truth, and so we err on the side of believing the liar. Trusting others is not only required, but it makes life easier to live. What matter if the cost is not detecting some who take advantage of that trust, for one might never know about it. It is only the paranoid who foregoes such peace of mind, and those whose lives are actually at some risk if they are not constantly alert to betrayal. Consistent with this formulation we (Ekman, Bugental, and Frank, unpublished data) obtained preliminary evidence that abused children living in an institutional setting were more accurate than other children in detecting lies from demeanor.

My fourth explanation is that we often want to be misled, we collude in the lie unwittingly because we have a stake in not knowing the truth.5 Consider two examples from spousal relationships. It may not be in the interest of a mother with a number of very young children to catch her mate’s lie which conceals his infidelity, particularly if he is having a fling in which he is not diverting resources which would otherwise go to her and her children. The philanderer does not want to be caught, so they both have an interest in the lie not being uncovered. A similar logic is at work in this next, more altruistic lie and collusive belief. A wife asks her husband, “Was there any other woman at the party whom you thought was more attractive than me?” He lies by claiming she was the most attractive when she was not. He does not want to

make her jealous, and he does not want to deal with her having such feelings, and she may want to believe she was the most attractive.

In some collusions the target who wants to believe the liar may not benefit from the lie or benefit only in the short run. Consider what was perhaps the most infamous example in this century of a target believing a liar who meant him harm. I refer to the meeting between the British Prime Minister, Nevelle Chamberlain, and Adolph Hitler, the Chancellor of Germany, on September 15, 1938.

The world watches, aware that this may be the last hope of avoiding another world war. (Just six

months earlier Hitler’s troops had marched into Austria, annexing it to Germany. England and

France had protested but done nothing further.) On September 12, three days before he is to meet

Chamberlain, Hitler demands to have part of Czechoslovakia annexed to Germans’ and incites

rioting in that country. Hitler has already secretly mobilized the German Army to attack

Czechoslovakia, but his army won’t be ready until the end of September. If he can keep the

Czechs from mobilizing their army for a few more weeks, Hitler will have the advantage of a

surprise attack. Stalling for time, Hitler conceals his war plans from Chamberlain, giving his

word that peace can be preserved if the Czechs will meet his demands. Chamberlain is fooled; he

tries to persuade the Czechs not to mobilize their army while there is still a chance to negotiate

with Hitler. After his meeting with Hitler, Chamberlain writes to his sister, ‘. . . in spite of the

hardness and ruthlessness I thought 1 saw in his face, I got the impression that here was a man

who could be relied upon when he had given his word . . . Defending his policies against those

who doubt Hitler’s word, Chamberlain five days later in a speech to Parliament explains that his

personal contact with Hitler allows him to say that Hitler ‘means what he says’ (Ekman, [1985]

1992, pp. 15, 16).

Hitler reportedly wrote, “The victor will not be asked afterward whether he told the truth. In starting and waging war it is not justice that matters but victory.” Why did Chamberlain believe Hitler? Not everyone did, there were many in the opposition party in Britain and elsewhere who recognized that Hitler was not a man of his word. Chamberlain unwittingly, I believe, colluded in Hitler’s lie because he had to believe Hitler. If Chamberlain were to have recognized Hitler’s lie, he would have to confront the fact that his policy of appeasement had put his country at grave risk. Since he had to face that fact just a few weeks later, one might ask why did he not recognize it during this meeting with Hitler? That would be rational but not psychological. Most of us operate on the unwritten principle of postponing having to confront anything which is very unpleasant. and we may do so by collusively overlooking a liar’s mistakes.

Chamberlain was not unique. The targets of lies, often unwittingly, collusively want to believe the liar. The same motive—not wanting to recognize impending disaster—explains why the businessman who mistakenly hired an embezzler continues to miss the signs of the embezzlement. Rationally speaking, the sooner he discovers the embezzlement the better, but psychologically that discovery will mean he must face not only his company’s losses, but his own mistake in having hired such a rascal. In a similar fashion, everyone but the cuckolded spouse may know what is happening. Or the pre-adolescent using hard drugs may be convinced that her parents surely must know what she is doing, while they unwittingly strive to avoid spotting the lies which would force them to deal with the possibility that they have failed as parents and now have a terrible struggle on their hands. One is nearly always better off in the

short run to cooperate with the lie, even if that means that the consequences tomorrow will be even worse.

A fifth explanation is based on Erving Goffman’s writings (1974). We are brought up to be polite in our interactions, not to steal information which is not given to us. A rather remarkable example of this is how we unwittingly avert our gaze when someone we are talking to cleans their ears or picks their nose. Goffman would also argue that the false message sometimes may be the more socially important message than the truth. It is the acknowledged information, the information for which the person who states it is willing to take responsibility. When the secretary who is miserable about a fight with her husband the previous night answers, “Just fine,” when her boss asks, “How are you this morning?” that false message may be the one relevant to the boss’ interactions with her. It tells him that she is going to do her job. The true message—that she is miserable—he may not care to know about at all as long as she does not intend to let it impair her job performance.

None of the explanations I have offered so far can explain why most members of the criminal justice and intelligence communities do so poorly in identifying liars from demeanor. Police and counter-intelligence interrogators are not taking a trusting stance with their suspects, they are not colluding in being misled, and they are willing to steal information not given to them. Why do they’ not do better in identifying liars from demeanor? I believe they are handicapped by a high base-rate and inadequate feedback. Most of the people they deal with probably are lying to them. Those with whom I have spoken estimate the base rate of lying as more than three-fourths. Such a high base rate is not optimal for learning to be alert to the subtle behavioral clues to deceit. Their orientation all too often is not how to spot the liar, but how to get the evidence to nail the liar. And when they make a mistake and learn that someone was wrongfully punished, that feedback comes too late, too far removed from the mistaken judgment to be corrective.

This suggests that if you expose people to a lower base-rate of lying, around 50 percent, and give them corrective feedback after each judgment they make, they might well learn how to accurately identify lies from demeanor. This is an experiment we are now planning. I do not expect that accuracy will reach one hundred percent, and for that reason I do not believe that judgments about who is lying should be allowable evidence in court. Such judgments, however, may provide a sounder basis for deciding, at least initially, whom to investigate further, and when to ask more questions to clarify why something unusual has been noticed.

Notes

1I am grateful to Helena Cronin, London School of Economics, for asking me why evolution had not prepared us to be better lie catchers, also to Mark Frank. Rutgers University, and Richard Schuster, University of Haifa, for their many helpful comments on this manuscript.

2 Helena Cronin raised this possibility.

3 I am grateful to Leda Cosmides and John Tooby, University of California, Berkeley, and to Richard Schuster, University of Haifa, for pointing this out.

4 I am grateful to Alison Gopnik, University of California, Berkeley, for suggesting this explanation.

5 For evidence consistent with my reasoning see Tooby and Cosmides, 1989.

References

Bok, C., Secrets (New York: Pantheon, 1982).

Bradley, M.T., “Choice and the Detection of Deception,” Perceptual and Motor Skills, 66 (1988): 43-8.

Cheney, D.L. and Seyfarth, How Monkeys See the World (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1990).

Cosmides, L. and Tooby, J., “Cognitive Adaptations for Social Exchange,” in J. Barkow, L.

Cosmides, and J. Tooby, eds., The Adapted Mind (New York: Oxford University Press,

1992).

DePaulo, B.M. and Pfeifer, R.L., “On-the-job Experience and Skill at Detecting Deception”

Journal of Applied Social Psychologv, 16 (1986): 249-67.

Ekman, P., Telling Lies: Clues to deceit in the marketplace marriage and politics, 2/e ([l985] New York: W.W. Norton. 1992).

Ekman, P., Frank, M., and O’Sullivan, M., “Detecting Deceit from Demeanor,” forthcoming. Ekman, P. and Friesen, W.V., “Detecting Deception From Body or Face,” Journal of Personality and Social Psvchology, 29 (1974):

288-98.

Ekman, P. and O’Sul]ivan, NI., “Who Can Catch a Liar,” American Psychologist, 46 (1991): 913-920.

Frank M. and Ekman, P., “The Ability to Detect Deceit Generalizes Across Deception Situations,” Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, forthcoming.

Ginton, A., Daie, N., Elaad, E., and Ben-Shakhar. G., “A Method for Evaluating the Use of the Polygraph in a Real-Life Situation” Journal of Applied Psychology, 67 (1982): 13 1-37.

Goffman, E., Frame Analysis (New York: Harper and Row. 1974).

Grafen, A., “Biological Signals as Handicaps,” Journal of Theoretical Biology, 144 (1990): 517-

46.

Kraut, R.E. and Poe, D., “On the Line: The Deception Judgments of Customs Inspectors and Lavmen,” Journal of Personality and Social Psychology. 39 (1980): 784-98.

Levine, T.R. and McCornack, S.A., “Linking Love and Lies: A Formal Test of the McCornack

and Parks Model of Deception Detection,” Journal of Social and Personal Relationships, 9 (1992): 143-54.

Sillars, A.L. and Scott, M.D., “Interpersonal Perception Between Intimates: An Integrative Review,” Human Communication Research, 10 (1983): 153-56.

Stiff, J., Corman, S., Krizek, B., and Snider, E., “Individual Differences and Changes in Nonverbal Behavior,” Communication Research, 21(1994): 555-581.

Toobv, J. and Cosmides, L., “The logic of threat,” Annual meeting of the Human Behavior and Evolution Society, Evanston, Illinois. 1989.

JAVA基础测试及答案

第一单元Java基础知识测样 班级___________姓名:_____________得分:_____________ 一、选择题(每题2分,共40分) 1、下面哪项可以得到数组元素的个数,java中定义数组名为abc,(B) A、abc.length() B、abc.length C、len(abc) D、ubound(abc) 2、构造方法何时被调用(B) A.类定义时 B.创建对象时 C.调用对象方法时 D.使用对象的变量时 3、下列语句片段int a=10,b=4,c=20,d=6;System.out.println(a++*b+c*--d);的结果为 (C) A.144 B.28 C.140 D.不能执行 4、下面哪个修饰符修饰的方法只能被本类中的其他方法使用(C) A、protected B、static C、private D、public 5、编译并运行下述程序段的结果是:(A)。 public class Test{ public static void main(String argv[]){ int[]count=new int[4]; System.out.println(count[4]);}} A.编译时错误B.运行时错误C.输出0D.输出null 6、在java的一个异常处理中,哪个语句块可以有多个(A) A、catch B、finally C、try D、throws 7、若在某一个类定义中定义有如下的方法: final void aFinalFunction(); 则该方法属于(C)。 A.本地方法B.静态方法C.最终方法D.抽象方法 9、类Test1定义如下: 1)public class Test1{ 2)public float aMethod(float a,float b){} 3) 4)}将以下哪种方法插入行3是不合法的。(B) A、public float aMethod(float a,float b,float c){} B、public float aMethod(float c,float d){} C、public int aMethod(int a,int b){} D、private float aMethod(int a,int b,int c){}

螺纹通止规

螺纹通止规 定是:螺纹止规进入螺纹不能超过2.5圈,一般的要实际不得超过2圈,并且用得力度不能大,我们的经验是用拇指和食指轻轻夹持螺纹规以刚好能转动螺纹规的力度为准.力大了就相当于在使用丝锥或牙板了,那样规就用不了几次了. 螺纹通止规 螺纹通止规是适用于标准规定型号的灯头作为灯用附件电光源产品时候的设计和生产、检验的工具设备。 用途 一般用于检验螺纹灯头或灯座的尺寸是否符合标准要求,分别检验螺纹灯头的通规和止规尺寸或灯座的通规或止规尺寸。 工作原理 具体检验要求及介绍详见中国人民国国家标准:GB/T1483.1-2008或 IEC60061-3:2004标准规定容。 操作方法 具体检验要求及介绍详见中国人民国国家标准:GB/T1483.1-2008或 IEC60061-3:2004标准规定容。 通止规

通止规,是量规的一种。作为度量标准,用于大批量的检验产品。 通止规是量具的一种,在实际生产批量的产品若采取用计量量具(如游标卡尺,千分表等有刻度的量具)逐个测量很费事.我们知道合格的产品是有一个度量围的.在这个围的都合格,所以人们便采取通规和止规来测量. 通止规种类 (一)对统一英制螺纹,外螺纹有三种螺纹等级:1A、2A和3A级,螺纹有三种等级:1B、2B和3B级,全部都是间隙配合。等级数字越高,配合越紧。在英制螺纹中,偏差仅规定1A和2A级,3A级的偏差为零,而且1A和2A级的等级偏差是相等的等级数目越大公差越小,如图所示:1B 2B 3B 螺纹基本中径3A 外螺纹2A 1A 1、1A和1B级,非常松的公差等级,其适用于外螺纹的允差配合。 2、2A和2B级,是英制系列机械紧固件规定最通用的螺纹公差等级。 3、3A和3B级,旋合形成最紧的配合,适用于公差紧的紧固件,用于安全性的关键设计。 4、对外螺纹来说,1A和2A级有一个配合公差,3A级没有。1A级公差比2A级公差大50,比3A级大75,对螺纹来说,2B级公差比2A公差大30。1B级比2B级大50,比3B级大75。 (二)公制螺纹,外螺纹有三种螺纹等级:4h、6h和6g,螺纹有三种螺纹等级:5H、6 H、7H。(日标螺纹精度等级分为I、II、III三级,通常状况下为II级)在公制螺纹中,H 和h的基本偏差为零。G的基本偏差为正值,e、f和g的基本偏差为负值。如图所示:公差G H 螺纹偏差基本中径外螺纹f g h e 1、H是螺纹常用的公差带位置,一般不用作表面镀层,或用极薄的磷化层。G位置基本偏差用于特殊场合,如较厚的镀层,一般很少用。 2、g常用来镀6-9um的薄镀层,如产品图纸要6h的螺栓,其镀前螺纹采用6g的公差带。 3、螺纹配合最好组合成H/g、H/h或G/h,对于螺栓、螺母等精制紧固件螺纹,标准推荐采用6H/6g的配合。 (三)螺纹标记M10×1–5g 6g M10×1–6H 顶径公差代号中径和顶径公差代号(相同)中径公差代号。 通止规是两个量具分为通规和止规.举个例子:M6-7h的螺纹通止规一头为通规(T)如果能顺利旋进被测螺纹孔则为合格,反之不合格需返工(也就是孔小了).然后用止规(Z)如果能顺利旋进被测螺纹孔2.5圈或以上则为不合格反之合格.且此时不合格的螺纹孔应报废,不能进行返工了.其中2.5圈为国家标准,若是出口件最多只能进1.5圈(国际标准).总之通规过止规不过为合格,通规止规都不过或通规止规都过则为不合格。

java异常试题

异常作业 一.填空题填空题 1.一个try语句块后必须跟( catch )语句块,( finally )语句块可以没有2.自定义异常类必须继承()类及其子类 3.异常处理机制允许根据具体的情况选择在何处处理异常,可以在()捕获并处理,也可以用throws子句把他交给()处理 二.选择题二.选择题 1. finally语句块中的代码() A.总是被执行 B.当try语句块后面没有catch时,finally中的代码才会执行 C.异常发生时才执行 D.异常没有发生时才被执行 2. 抛出异常应该使用的关键字是() A.throw B.catch C.finally D.throws 3. 自定义异常类时,可以继承的类是() A.Error B.Applet C.Exception及其子类 D.AssertionError 4. 在异常处理中,将可能抛出异常的方法放在()语句块中 A.throws B.catch C.try D.finally 5. 对于try{……}catch子句的排列方式,下列正确的一项是() A.子类异常在前,父类异常在后 B.父类异常在前,子类异常在后 C.只能有子类异常 D.父类异常与子类异常不能同时出现 6. 使用catch(Exception e)的好处是() A.只会捕获个别类型的异常 B.捕获try语句块中产生的所有类型的异常 C.忽略一些异常 D.执行一些程序 三.简答题三.简答题 1. try/catch/finally如何使用? 2. throw/throws有什么联系和区别? 3. 如何自定义异常类? 4. 谈谈final、finally的区别和作用 5. 如果try{}里有一个return语句,那么紧跟在这个try后的finally{}里的代码会不会被执行?

螺纹通止规要求螺纹通规通

螺纹通止规要求螺纹通规通,止规止。 但是如果螺纹通规止,说明什么? 螺纹止规通,又说明什么? 我也来说两句查看全部回复 最新回复 ?wpc (2008-11-07 20:11:20) 在牙型正确的前提下螺纹通止规检测螺纹中径 ?lobont (2008-11-08 11:16:32) 对外螺纹而言,螺纹通规是做到中径上偏差,所以能通过就表示产品合格,通不过就表示螺纹做大了,要再修一刀; 螺纹止规做到中径下偏差,所以只能通过2~3牙,如果也通过,就表示外螺纹做小了,产品成为废品 ?qubin8512 (2008-11-18 15:36:05) 螺纹赛规与螺纹环规主要测量螺纹的中径。 ?datafield (2008-11-29 19:12:51) 检具不是万能的,只是方便而已。具体没什么的我有在哪本书上看过,是一本螺纹手册上的。 ?ZYC007 (2009-2-09 20:31:13) 在牙型正确的前提下螺纹通止规检测螺纹中径。 对外螺纹而言,但是如果螺纹通规止,说明螺纹中径大;螺纹止规通,又说明螺纹中径小。 ?WWCCJJ (2009-3-19 09:27:19) 检测的是螺纹的中径,螺纹检测规在检定时,也是检测其中径. ?tanjiren (2009-3-20 22:23:06) 螺纹通止规只能检测螺纹的作用中径,大径和底径等均无法准确测量出来. ?月夜(2009-4-01 21:47:13) 用来测量中径 ?丽萍(2009-4-02 10:11:41)

只能检测工件螺纹的中径 yg196733456 (2009-4-03 09:15:56)原来是测中径的知道了

(完整版)java测试试卷(三)

JAVA语言基础内部测试题 一.单项选择题(请选择最符合题目要求的答案)(每题2分) 1、在JAVA中,以下(c )类的对象以键-值的方式存储对象 A、java.util.List B、java.util.ArrayList C、java.util.HashMap D、java.util.LinkedList 2、给定如下所示的JAVA代码,则运行时,会产生( b )类型的异常 String s = null; s.concat("abc"); A.ArithmeticException B.NullPointerException C.IOException D.ClassNotFoundException 3、给定如下Java 程序代码片段,编译运行这段代码,结果是( b )。 java.util.HashMap map = new java.util.HashMap(); map.put("name",null); map.put("name","Jack"); System.out.println(map.get("name")); A.null B.Jack C.nullJack D.运行时出现异常 4、分析如下Java代码,编译运行后将输出(b )。 public class Test{ public Test(){} static void print(ArrayList al){ al.add(2); al=new ArrayList(); al.add(3); al.add(4); } public static void main(String[]args){ Test test=new Test(); ArrayList al=new ArrayList(); al.add(1); print(al); System.out.println(al.get(1)); } } A、1 B、2 C、3 D、4

NPT螺纹以及检测方法详解

N P T螺纹以及检测方法详 解 Prepared on 22 November 2020

一、目的:规范公司技术员,检验员,操作员对NPT螺纹的了解。 二、适用范围:适用于公司任何NPT螺纹类产品,参考资料为通用管螺 纹和国家标准GB/T12716-2011。 三、目录 1、NPT和NPTF介绍 2、螺纹技术参数参数讲解 3、NPT与NPTF加工工艺 4、NPT和NPTF的检测方法 四、内容: NPT和NPTF螺纹介绍 NPT 是 National (American) Pipe Thread 的缩写,属於美国标准的 60 度锥管 密封螺纹,用於北美地区,美国标准为13)通用管螺纹.国家标准可查阅 GB/T12716-2011。NPTF:美制干密封圆锥管螺。NPTF = National Pipe Thread Fine 称之为一般用途的锥管螺纹,这也是我们以前称之为的布氏锥螺纹。NPTF 螺纹称之为干密封式锥管螺纹,它连接密封的原理是在没有润滑剂或密封填 料情况下完全依靠螺纹自身形成密封,设计意图是使内、外螺纹牙的侧面、 牙顶和牙底同时接触,来达到密封的目的。它们两者的牙型角、斜度等指标 都是相同的,关键是牙顶和牙底的削平高度不一样,所以,量规的设计也是 不一样的。NPTF干密封管螺纹的牙形精度比NPT螺纹高,旋合时不用任何 填料,完全依靠螺纹自身形成密封,螺纹间无任何密封介质。干密封管螺纹 规定有较为严格的公差,属精密型螺纹,仅用在特殊场合。这种螺纹有较高 的强度和良好的密封性,在具有薄截面的脆硬材料上采用此螺纹可以减少断 裂现象。NPTF内、外螺纹牙顶与牙底间没有间隙,是过盈配合,而NPT螺 纹是过渡配合。NPTF螺纹主要用于高温高压对密封要求严格的场所。NPT

正确的美容护肤步骤

正确的美容护肤步骤 正确的美容护肤步骤 洗脸: 白天只用洗面奶就行了,晚上的话,先用卸妆乳,再用洗面奶。化妆过或者使用过隔离霜、防晒霜就一定要卸妆。 使用爽肤水: 用化妆棉蘸爽肤水擦脸,能起到二次清洁的作用,如果想保湿就用手直接拍脸上,但是不能太重,轻拍就可以。无论用哪种方法,都要用到皮肤不干为止。 使用精华液: 先将手部搓热,将精华液均匀的搽在脸上,注意精华成分要避开眼周肌肤,用手掌轻轻按压面部的u区,按照由下到上、由外至内的方式轻柔按压,确保精华成分的完全吸收,t区也用相同的方式重复。最后利用手指肚轻轻敲弹脸部的肌肤,100下为一组,进行3组即可。 保湿: 根据自己的肤质选择不同的保湿护肤品。秋冬季节皮肤干的话就用霜,白天用日霜,晚上用晚霜。春夏皮肤比较湿润用乳就行了。如果是晚上护肤不敷面膜的话,这是最后一步哦! 隔离: .取适量隔离霜于两颊处,额头,下巴,用中指和无名指两个

个指腹,从脸颊处向下拉伸;.扩展到额头中央,再向两边拉伸,随后轻轻拍打直至完全吸收。 防晒: 防晒霜应该根据自己的需要和防晒霜的spf与pa值去选择,防晒霜的功效时间长短是取决于spf值得大小,以spf15为例它的功效时间是(15×10分钟=150分钟)也就是说spf15它表示的是防晒功效是10分钟的15倍。并不是说时间越长越好,因为时间长对皮肤的负担就会越重,如果你并不是长时间从事户外工作或运动的,就不建议你用高倍的了。 正确的男士护肤步骤 步骤一:做好控油清洁工作 男性的皮肤跟女性的皮肤还是有很多不同点的,因此,在护肤的时候也是有所不同,男士皮脂分泌和汗腺都比女性发达,因此,男性的皮肤很容易遭遇毛孔阻塞的现象,从而产生暗疮和粉刺。 男士想要肌肤更健康,这个时候一定要选择用正确的洗面产品,早晚一定要认真清洁肌肤,对于油性肌肤的男性来说,洗脸的次数不能太多,如果说洗脸次数过多的话,只会让男性的肌肤越干,建议男性每天洗脸两次就可以了。 步骤二:收缩毛孔 男士在清洁完脸部以后,这个时候面部皮肤还处于水分易蒸发并且没有保护的状态,此时如果你想很好的控油保湿,不妨使用化妆水,化妆水能起到很好的补水保湿功效,并且还能很好的防止水分的蒸发,达到很好的锁水,让你的肌肤喝足水,这样一

通止规的用法及管理

通止规的用法及管理 1、止规 使用前:应经相关检验计量机构检验计量合格后,方可投入生产现场使用。 使用时:应注意被测螺纹公差等级及偏差代号与环规标识公差等级、偏差代号相同(如M24*1.5-6h与M24*1.5-5g两种环规外形相同,其螺纹公差带不相同,错用后将产生批量不合格品)。 检验测量过程:首先要清理干净被测螺纹油污及杂质,然后在环规与被测螺纹对正后,用大母指与食指转动环规,旋入螺纹长度在2个螺距之内为合格,否则判为不合格品。 2、通规 使用前:应经相关检验计量机构检验计量合格后,方可投入生产现场使用。 使用时:应注意被测螺纹公差等级及偏差代号与环规标识的公差等级、偏差代号相同(如M24*1.5-6h与M24*1.5-5g两种环规外形相同,其螺纹公差带不相同,错用后将产生批量不合格品)。 检验测量过程:首先要清理干净被测螺纹塞规油污及杂质,然后在环规与被测螺纹对正后,用大母指与食指转动环规,使其在自由状态下旋合通过螺纹全部长度判定合格,否则以不通判定。 3、注意事项 在用量具应在每个工作日用校对塞规计量一次。经校对塞规计量超差或者达到计量器具周检期限的环规,由计量管理人员收回、标识隔离并作相应的处理措施。 可调节螺纹环规经调整后,测量部位会产生失圆,此现象由计量修复人员经螺纹磨削加工后再次计量鉴定,各尺寸合格后方可投入使用。 报废环规应标识隔离并及时处理,不得流入生产现场。 4、维护与保养 量具(环规)使用完毕后,应及时清理干净测量部位附着物,存放在规定的量具盒内。生产现场在用量具应摆放在工艺定置位置,轻拿轻放,以防止磕碰而损坏测量表面。 严禁将量具作为切削工具强制旋入螺纹,避免造成早期磨损。可调节螺纹环规严禁非计量工作人员随意调整,确保量具的准确性。环规长时间不用,应交计量管理部门妥善保管。

java考试

编程题,每题5分 1.编程计算N的累加(求1+2+..+n的和)的程序,一个使用递归 方法,一个不用递归方法 2.编程显示某一文件目录下的所有文件名; public void showName(File f){} 3.定义一个文件d:/info.txt,在文件中存储2行文本,写一个程序, 读取文件中的全部文本(使用BufferedReader); 4.定义一个方法,功能是从10个人名中随机挑出5个人名,并输 出(5分) Public void pickNames(); 5.设计两个个线程模拟存取款操作,其中一个线程每次随机存 1~1000元钱,另外一个线程取1-1000元钱,如果余额不足,则 取款失败,提示余额不足。写出程序(考虑并发问题)。 6.制作一个字符串数组,每个元素都有一些随意输入的数字和字母 组成,要求找出里面每个数字,然后求出他们的和,比如 {"adf1f23","ju34ui21"}第一个元素的数字是123,第二个数字是 3421他们的和是3421+123 =3544; 7.定义一个学生类Student,属性有age(年纪),name(姓名),score (分数),实例化6个对象,放在集合中, .有如下Student 对象 其中,classNum 表示学生的班号,例如“class05”。 有如下List List list = new ArrayList(); list.add(new Student(“Tom”, 18, 100, “class05”)); list.add(new Student(“Jerry”, 22, 70, “class04”)); list.add(new Student(“Owen”, 25, 90, “class05”)); list.add(new Student(“Jim”, 30,80 , “class05”)); list.add(new Student(“Steve”, 28, 66, “class06”)); list.add(new Student(“Kevin”, 24, 100, “class04”)); 在这个list 的基础上,完成下列要求: 1)统计出总班级数 2)统计每个班级的平均分和人数 3)按学生的成绩排序(成绩相同按年纪)排序输出; 8.有一个ArrayList集合,集合中的元素分别 {1,2,3,6,8,7,7,8,2,2,1,2},将重复的数字找到,并按数字的大小排序 输出输出,格式是 1:2次 2:4次 3:1次 6:1次 7:3次 8:2次

异常习题

1.java中用来抛出异常的关键字是() A、try B、catch C、throw D、finally 1.关于异常,下列说法正确的是(A) A、异常是一种对象 B、一旦程序运行,异常将被创建 C、为了保证程序运行速度,要尽量避免异常控制 D、以上说法都不对 3()类是所有异常类的父类。 A、Throwable B、Error C、Exception D、AWTError 4..java语言中,下列哪一子句是异常处理的出口( ) A、try{…}子句 B、catch{…}子句 C、finally{…}子句 D、以上说法都不对 5.对于catch子句的排列,下列哪种是正确的( ) A、父类在先,子类在后 B、子类在先,父类在后 C、有继承关系的异常不能在同一个try程序段内 D、先有子类,其他如何排列都无关 6在异常处理中,如释放资源、关闭文件、关闭数据库等由( )来完成。 A、try子句 B、catch子句 C、finally子句 D、throw子句 7当方法遇到异常又不知如何处理时,下列哪种说法是正确的( ) A、捕获异常 B、抛出异常 C、声明异常 D、嵌套异常 8.一个异常将终止( A) A、整个程序 B、叧终止抛出异常的方法 C、产生异常的try块 D、上面的说法都对二.填空题 1、catch子句都带一个参数,该参数是某个异常的类及其变量名,catch用该参数去与______对象的类进行匹配。 2、java虚拟机能自动处理_______异常。 3、变量属性是描述变量的作用域,按作用域分类,变量有局部变量、类变量、方法参数和_______ 4、捕获异常要求在程序的方法中预先声明,在调用方法时用_____语句捕获并处理。 5、java语言认为那些可预料和不可预料的出错称为________ 6、按异常处理不同可以分为1_______,2______3_______4_____几种。 7、抛出异常的程序代码可以是_自定义的异常_____或者是JDK中的某个类,还可以是JVM. 8、抛出异常、生成异常对象都可以通过_________语句实现。 9、捕获异常的统一出口通过_________语句实现。 10、java语言的类库中提供了一个________类,所有的异常都必须是它的实例 三、判断题 1. ( ) 程序中抛出异常时(throw …),只能抛出自己定义的异常对象。 2. ( ) 一个异常处理中finally语句块只能有一个或者可以没有。 3.( )异常类对象代表当前出现的一个具体异常。 4.( )java语言中的所有异常类都是https://www.360docs.net/doc/7e4198066.html,ng.Throwable的子类。 5.( ) 如果异常发生时,没有捕获异常的代码,程序会正常执行。

通止规的用法及管理

通止规的用法及管理 令狐采学 1、止规 使用前:应经相关检验计量机构检验计量合格后,方可投入生产现场使用。 使用时:应注意被测螺纹公差等级及偏差代号与环规标识公差等级、偏差代号相同(如M24*1.56h与M24*1.55g两种环规外形相同,其螺纹公差带不相同,错用后将产生批量不合格品)。 检验测量过程:首先要清理干净被测螺纹油污及杂质,然后在环规与被测螺纹对正后,用大母指与食指转动环规,旋入螺纹长度在2个螺距之内为合格,否则判为不合格品。 2、通规 使用前:应经相关检验计量机构检验计量合格后,方可投入生

产现场使用。 使用时:应注意被测螺纹公差等级及偏差代号与环规标识的公差等级、偏差代号相同(如M24*1.56h与M24*1.55g两种环规外形相同,其螺纹公差带不相同,错用后将产生批量不合格品)。 检验测量过程:首先要清理干净被测螺纹塞规油污及杂质,然后在环规与被测螺纹对正后,用大母指与食指转动环规,使其在自由状态下旋合通过螺纹全部长度判定合格,否则以不通判定。 3、注意事项 在用量具应在每个工作日用校对塞规计量一次。经校对塞规计量超差或者达到计量器具周检期限的环规,由计量管理人员收回、标识隔离并作相应的处理措施。 可调节螺纹环规经调整后,测量部位会产生失圆,此现象由计量修复人员经螺纹磨削加工后再次计量鉴定,各尺寸合格后方

可投入使用。 报废环规应标识隔离并及时处理,不得流入生产现场。 4、维护与保养 量具(环规)使用完毕后,应及时清理干净测量部位附着物,存放在规定的量具盒内。生产现场在用量具应摆放在工艺定置位置,轻拿轻放,以防止磕碰而损坏测量表面。 严禁将量具作为切削工具强制旋入螺纹,避免造成早期磨损。可调节螺纹环规严禁非计量工作人员随意调整,确保量具的准确性。环规长时间不用,应交计量管理部门妥善保管。

java异常处理试题及答案

异常处理练习题 一、选择题 中用来抛出异常的关键字是(C) A、try B、catch C、throw D、finally 2.关于异常,下列说法正确的是(A) A、异常是一种对象 B、一旦程序运行,异常将被创建 C、为了保证程序运行速度,要尽量避免异常控制 D、以上说法都丌对 3.(A)类是所有异常类的父类。 A、Throwable B、Error C、Exception D、AWTError 语言中,下列哪一子句是异常处理的出口(C) A、try{…}子句 B、catch{…}子句 C、finally{…}子句 D、以上说法都丌对 5.下列程序的执行,说法错误的是(C) public class MultiCatch { public static void main(String args[]) { try { int a=; int b=42/a; int c[]={1}; c[42]=99; } catch(ArithmeticException e) { 除0异常:”+e); } catch(ArrayIndexOutOfBoundsException e) { 数组超越边界异常:”+e); } } } A、程序将输出第15行的异常信息 B、程序第10行出错 C、程序将输出“b=42”

D、程序将输出第15和19行的异常信息 6.下列程序的执行,说法正确的是(D) class ExMulti { static void procedure() { try { int c[]={1}; c[42]=99; } catch(ArrayIndexOutOfBoundsException e) { 数组超越界限异常:”+e); } } public static void main(String args[]) { try { procedure(); int a=; int b=42/a; } catch(ArithmeticException e) { 除0异常:”+e); } } } A、程序只输出第12行的异常信息 B、程序只输出第26行的异常信息 C、程序将不输出异常信息 D、程序将输出第12行和第26行的异常信息 7.下面程序抛出了一个“异常”并捕捉它。请在横线处填入适当内容完成程序。class TrowsDemo { static void procedure() throws IllegalAccessExcepton { procedure”); throw__new_____IllegalAccessException(“demo”);

最佳的护肤基本步骤分为5个步骤

最佳的护肤基本步骤分为5个步骤:清洁—调整皮肤纹理—爽肤—均衡滋润—保护 1.清洁 皮肤清洁是保养的基础,可以彻底地去除脸上的化妆品,表面油渍和污垢。 清洁的手法:用中指和无名指的指腹顺由下向上,由内向外轻柔面部,避开眼周。然后用温水冲洗,用干毛巾或者化妆棉轻轻吸干面部。 卸装是清洁之前重要的一步:如果有彩妆,则应该先卸除残妆。 2.调理 角质层过厚,肌肤失去通透感,变得粗糙晦暗,而且会阻碍护肤营养品的吸收。这就需要养成定期去除堆积死皮的护肤习惯,让肌肤恢复通透柔嫩。一周两次敷面膜,可以帮助剥除表面干燥细胞,使皮肤纹理光华,呈现清新、光彩,并促进对营养品的吸收。

涂抹/清洗面膜的手法:以向上、向外的手势将面膜平敷在洁净的脸部,避开眼周和唇部。静待10分钟。然后用清水洗去。注意,如果是敏感肌肤8分钟即可。 3.爽肤 使用爽肤水的作用是补水保湿,同时可以软化角质,再次清洁肌肤,促进后续润肤营养吸收。平衡PH 值,增加肌肤的柔软感和湿润度。还可以帮助收缩毛孔。 爽肤水的用法:沾湿化妆棉,避开眼部,轻轻擦拭脸部和颈部,直到化妆棉上没有污垢及残留化妆品的痕迹为止。这样不仅可以加强二次清洁的效果,更有效促进后续营养吸收。 4.均衡滋养 这是指用乳液或面霜的保养步骤。能给肌肤补充必需的水分和养分,充分滋润皮肤,保持肌肤柔润光滑。

均衡滋润的用法:用中指和无名指的指腹,轻轻地以朝上和朝外的方式涂抹。通常眼霜应该用在面霜之前的步骤,涂抹眼周部位时,请用轻柔的无名指指腹。 5.保护 使用粉底,避免灰尘和污染物与皮肤接触,保护皮肤,并给与皮肤光滑、匀称的光彩。 保护的用法:取适量,先用五点法,点在额头、鼻子、两颊和下巴处。然后用中指无名指指腹或海绵,将粉底轻点,分散开,然后轻轻将粉底向外向下推开、抹匀。 一、选好洁肤品 适合自己的洗面奶在使用后皮肤清爽、微涩(但不脱皮)、皮肤色泽变得淡化(因去角质的缘故,有轻微增白之短暂功效)。

正确的化妆品使用步骤(教程)

正确的化妆品使用步骤(教程) 正确的化妆品使用步骤(教程) 化妆品你也许很熟悉,像欧莱雅、玉兰油、兰蔻、雅诗兰黛等等,尽人皆知,但是,你知道怎样去使用它们么?也许有人说,直接涂脸上就行了,错!和其他东西一样,化妆品也有正确的,规定的使用方法,方法不得当,则事倍功半,还要有一个正确的使用顺序,否则你用了也许没有效果,到时候就会说,哎呀,这个牌子的化妆品不行,还是换其他牌子的吧,其实这就是许多外行人的通病,下面为大家一一讲解。正确顺序是-洁面乳-化妆水-乳液-精华素-眼霜-面霜-隔离霜 详细步骤讲解: 1.洁面 选择:干性肌肤最好选择乳液状,混合性肌肤和油性肌肤则要选择泡沫丰富并且细腻的摩丝型洁面产品才能更深层的清洁毛细孔。 用法:乳液状无泡沫型的,先用温热水轻擦脸,这样使毛孔张开,用洗面奶均匀洗脸,按摩脸部。然后用温水洗清,还有特别要注意发际是否有洗面奶还未洗去,最后就是用冷水拍脸,使毛孔紧缩,用毛巾轻擦掉水就行了。有泡沫状的和前面一样,只是使用时要先把洗面奶先放手上,使其泡沫丰富,然后再放脸上轻揉,这一点非常重要,否则会浪费洗面奶,而且达不到预期的效果。

2.化妆水 选择:化妆品使用中非常重要,不可或缺的一部,可以说,没有它,以下的一切步骤都是徒劳,无用功!它可以滋润皮肤,清洁及清爽皮肤; 分弱碱性化妆水和弱酸性化妆水两种,前者使皮肤柔软,缓和表皮呼吸,亦可做卸妆用。它能打开毛孔,为下一步皮肤吸收精华素的营养作准备。 用法: 洗脸后用毛巾擦干,要立刻涂上化妆水。在洗完脸后30秒到2分钟内,是使用保湿品或化妆水的最佳时机,因为它们能将皮肤内的含水量瞬间提高。 涂抹时要从眼睛周围、脸颊等容易干燥的地方开始,满脸都要涂抹均匀,最后用手掌轻轻按压帮助吸收。 3.乳液 选择:用于滋润皮肤,依肌肤性质又分为油性、干性、中性、混合性及敏感肌肤用。干性肌肤可以选择质地粘稠一点的,油性肌肤则要选择质地轻盈一点的。

护肤正确的步骤

护肤正确的步骤 护肤三大步骤 1.清洁:崇尚“高清爽” 现代男士的生活节奏繁忙且充满动感,长期劳累奔波,需要随时随地保持旺盛的精力。但汗水与油腻便好像男人的“尾后虫”,仿佛永远也甩不掉,所以,清洁乃男士护肤的第一要义,“高清爽”的感觉能回复男人的潇洒本色!用男士专用的洁面产品,只要像刷牙一样,每日2次,每次3分钟,就能让自己的肌肤在那些柔柔滑滑的泡沫里,在彻底渗透、去除污垢、汗水和多余油脂后,找回“清爽”的感受。剃须后的皮肤护理是男士护肤的重要步骤。 2.清理:我要“最舒适” 清洁过后的第二步,就是清理皮层。男人一般很少使用紧肤水,其实它就像须后水一样十分必要。紧肤水可以帮助进一步清除表皮残余油脂、收敛毛孔并保持肌肤弱酸性的ph值,有些含保湿因子的紧肤水更能进一步柔化皮肤,在洁面、剃须后使用,感觉更加舒适,还能有效防止因剃须引起的“内生须”或过敏现象。 3.滋润:追求“零负担” 男人在护肤上总是很怕脸上有负担,他们讨厌面部被护肤品“糊”着的感觉,所以,追求“零负担”是男士好产品的标准之一。清爽型的润肤露,不油腻,会让脸部感觉轻松并迅速渗透,形成一层保护膜,有效锁住肌肤内水分,给肌肤持久的润泽。

错误的护肤方法 除肌肤自身因素以外,不当的护肤品使用方法也会导致肌肤无法吸收养分。很多护肤品从外观上看很相似,但它们的效能、用途、用法却很不一样。在购买和使用护肤品时,应根据肌肤的状况和需要,否则就会让营养白白流失,肌肤却得不到养护。 1、清洁太匆匆 通过彻底清洁,可使面部的肌肤卸下各种负担,让营养物质与表皮细胞零距离地接触。洁面还能让肌肤软化,从而角质层可以吸收更多水分,渗透和吸收能力都会加强,但错误的洁面方法就很难达到这一效果。 错误示例:许多人在清洁肌肤的时候马马虎虎,只是匆匆涂抹以后,便用清水将泡沫洗去,角质层没有得到软化,护肤品中的营养物质根本来不及渗透和吸收。还有的人甚至连肌肤表层的油脂和污垢都没有洗干净,滞留的油脂和污垢不但损害肌肤,还会形成一个闭合的屏障,影响后续护肤品中养分的渗透和吸收。 正确方法:一般来讲,清洁肌肤时一定要有耐心,尽量把每一寸肌肤都照顾到。可先用含有除垢成分的护肤品将肌肤表层的皮脂、污垢洗去,再用含营养成分的洗面奶以按摩方式涂抹在脸上,肌肤吸收营养物质的同时,还能促进皮下的血液循环,从而加速肌肤新陈代谢,对于养分渗入皮内、柔润肌肤也更为有利。 护肤肌肤类型示例:油性肌肤 step1卸妆;step2深层清洁啫喱;step3控油洁面乳。 2、护肤乱序 护肤包括深层护肤和表层护肤两种,这两种方式的护肤品功

通止规的用法及管理修订稿

通止规的用法及管理 WEIHUA system office room 【WEIHUA 16H-WEIHUA WEIHUA8Q8-

通止规的用法及管理 1、止规 使用前:应经相关检验计量机构检验计量合格后,方可投入生产现场使用。 使用时:应注意被测螺纹公差等级及偏差代号与环规标识公差等级、偏差代号相同(如M24*与M24*两种环规外形相同,其螺纹公差带不相同,错用后将产生批量不合格品)。 检验测量过程:首先要清理干净被测螺纹油污及杂质,然后在环规与被测螺纹对正后,用大母指与食指转动环规,旋入螺纹长度在2个螺距之内为合格,否则判为不合格品。 2、通规 使用前:应经相关检验计量机构检验计量合格后,方可投入生产现场使用。 使用时:应注意被测螺纹公差等级及偏差代号与环规标识的公差等级、偏差代号相同(如M24*与M24*两种环规外形相同,其螺纹公差带不相同,错用后将产生批量不合格品)。 检验测量过程:首先要清理干净被测螺纹塞规油污及杂质,然后在环规与被测螺纹对正后,用大母指与食指转动环规,使其在自由状态下旋合通过螺纹全部长度判定合格,否则以不通判定。 3、注意事项

在用量具应在每个工作日用校对塞规计量一次。经校对塞规计量超差或者达到计量器具周检期限的环规,由计量管理人员收回、标识隔离并作相应的处理措施。 可调节螺纹环规经调整后,测量部位会产生失圆,此现象由计量修复人员经螺纹磨削加工后再次计量鉴定,各尺寸合格后方可投入使用。 报废环规应标识隔离并及时处理,不得流入生产现场。 4、维护与保养 量具(环规)使用完毕后,应及时清理干净测量部位附着物,存放在规定的量具盒内。生产现场在用量具应摆放在工艺定置位置,轻拿轻放,以防止磕碰而损坏测量表面。 严禁将量具作为切削工具强制旋入螺纹,避免造成早期磨损。可调节螺纹环规严禁非计量工作人员随意调整,确保量具的准确性。环规长时间不用,应交计量管理部门妥善保管。

java虚拟机的原理和作用

Java虚拟机 一、什么是Java虚拟机 Java虚拟机是一个想象中的机器,在实际的计算机上通过软件模拟来实现。Java虚拟机有自己想象中的硬件,如处理器、堆栈、寄存器等,还具有相应的指令系统。 1.为什么要使用Java虚拟机 Java语言的一个非常重要的特点就是与平台的无关性。而使用Java虚拟机是实现这一特点的关键。一般的高级语言如果要在不同的平台上运行,至少需要编译成不同的目标代码。而引入Java语言虚拟机后,Java语言在不同平台上运行时不需要重新编译。Java语言使用模式Java虚拟机屏蔽了与具体平台相关的信息,使得Java语言编译程序只需生成在Java虚拟机上运行的目标代码(字节码),就可以在多种平台上不加修改地运行。Java虚拟机在执行字节码时,把字节码解释成具体平台上的机器指令执行。 2.谁需要了解Java虚拟机 Java虚拟机是Java语言底层实现的基础,对Java语言感兴趣的人都应对Java虚拟机有个大概的了解。这有助于理解Java语言的一些性质,也有助于使用Java语言。对于要在特定平台上实现Java虚拟机的软件人员,Java语言的编译器作者以及要用硬件芯片实现Java虚拟机的人来说,则必须深刻理解Java 虚拟机的规范。另外,如果你想扩展Java语言,或是把其它语言编译成Java语言的字节码,你也需要深入地了解Java虚拟机。 3.Java虚拟机支持的数据类型 Java虚拟机支持Java语言的基本数据类型如下: byte://1字节有符号整数的补码 short://2字节有符号整数的补码 int://4字节有符号整数的补码 long://8字节有符号整数的补码 float://4字节IEEE754单精度浮点数 double://8字节IEEE754双精度浮点数 char://2字节无符号Unicode字符 几乎所有的Java类型检查都是在编译时完成的。上面列出的原始数据类型的数据在Java执行时不需要用硬件标记。*作这些原始数据类型数据的字节码(指令)本身就已经指出了*作数的数据类型,例如iadd、ladd、fadd和dadd指令都是把两个数相加,其*作数类型别是int、long、 float和double。虚拟机没有给boolean(布尔)类型设置单独的指令。boolean型的数据是由integer指令,包括integer 返回来处理的。boolean型的数组则是用byte数组来处理的。虚拟机使用IEEE754格式的浮点数。不支持IEEE格式的较旧的计算机,在运行 Java数值计算程序时,可能会非常慢。 虚拟机支持的其它数据类型包括: object//对一个Javaobject(对象)的4字节引用 returnAddress//4字节,用于jsr/ret/jsr-w/ret-w指令 注:Java数组被当作object处理。 虚拟机的规范对于object内部的结构没有任何特殊的要求。在Sun公司的实现中,对object的引用是一个句柄,其中包含一对指针:一个指针指向该object的方法表,另一个指向该object的数据。用Java

夏天晚上护肤步骤

夏天晚上护肤步骤

夏天晚上护肤步骤 天天面对电脑工作,再加上夏天紫外线强烈等原因,很多女性的皮肤变得越来越差劲。下面我给大家介绍,希望对你有用! Step 1:基本净肤不可少 经过一日的辛劳奔波,肌肤积聚了不少尘埃和污垢,妨碍新陈代谢,如果我们不彻底深层洁净毛孔内的杂质,就会引发暗疮、粉刺、肌肤暗哑等问题。所以,切记保养肌肤的第 1步:洗面前,先要深层洁肤。成分温和的洁肤油 Deep Cleansing Oil,肯定是任何类型肌肤都适合的百搭选择。别以为洁肤油一定很油腻,其油性 成分能彻底溶解毛孔内的油脂、污垢和化妆,彻底洁净毛孔。配合轻轻打圈按摩的方式洗脸,亦有助洁肤油溶解毛孔内的杂质。 Step 2:温和清洁表层肌肤 深层洁净毛孔之后,还要以具有滋润效能的洁面产品来清洁肌肤。很多人都对洗面抱有错误的观念,以为用力洗擦就能够彻底洗净污垢,殊不知这样却会损害纤细的肌肤组织。同样地,有些人喜欢以温水洗脸,却不

知水温过高亦会伤害肌肤。因此以接近肌肤温度的水洗脸最佳。 正确的洗面方法其实很简单,只要先湿润双手,以洁面皂或洁面乳在手心搓揉出泡沫,再将泡沫覆盖脸部轻轻按摩,让泡沫温柔地带走肌肤上的污垢。此外,按摩亦要适得其法,许多人洗脸时,都只是无意识地摩擦肌肤,粗略地洗过一遍就算了,於是面颊等容易清洗的部位就会经常被用力摩擦,反之鼻翼和额角等较难洗净的地方却被马虎带过,这样不单不能彻底洗净隐藏的污垢,更加是导致混合性肌肤的原因之一,千万要留意! Step 3:为肌肤补充足够水分 洗面后,肌肤上的污垢完全清除了,但与此同时,保护肌肤表面的皮脂膜亦会一并被洗去,导致肌肤的水分和油脂含量急剧下降。如果经常处於这个状态的话,肌肤就会逐渐变得乾燥粗糙,因此洗脸后必须立即补充水分。一般的美肌水都有补湿和软化角质层的效用,可以防止水分蒸发和收细毛孔。这个步骤非常重要,因为角质层具锁水、防御外界污物入侵和阻挡紫外线伤害的功能,是保护肌肤的第一道屏障。 美肌水除了补湿之外,亦有针对不同肌肤的问题,加入美白、抗氧化和防UV等原素和功能,你可以按照自己的肌肤性质和需要,配合不同的护肤品使用。 Step 4:锁水修护平衡肌肤 既然美肌水已经补充了足够的水分,那麼肌肤保养工作是否已经完成

螺纹规使用方法

螺纹规使用方法 一、目的 规范塞规、环规使用的操作方法,保证测量结果的准确性。螺纹塞规使用者应根据操作规范要求,确保操作过程正确,并负责仪器的维护和保养。 二、说明 螺纹规又称螺纹通止规、螺纹量规,通常用来检验判定螺纹的尺寸是否合格。 螺纹规根据所检验内外螺纹分为螺纹塞规和螺纹环规,目前我们所使用的只有螺纹塞规。 图1 三、使用方法 1、选择螺纹规时,应选择与被测螺纹相匹配的规格。 2、使用前,先清理干净螺纹规和被测螺纹表面的油污、杂质等。 3、使用时,使螺纹规的通端(止端)与被测螺纹对正后,用大拇指与食指转动螺纹规或被 测零件,使其在自由状态下旋转。通常情况下(无被测零件的螺纹的图示说明时),螺纹 规(通端)的通规可以在被测螺纹的任意位置转动,通过全部螺纹长度则判定为合格,否 则为不合格品;在螺纹规(止端)的止规与被测螺纹对正后,旋入螺纹长度在2个螺距之 内止住为合格,不可强行用力通过,否则判为不合格品。(有被测零件的图示说明时,应 按照图示说明做判定。) 图2 图3 图中英文字母“GO”或“T”:表 示螺纹塞规的通端。 图中“G 3/8-19”或“M3 6H” 表示该螺纹规规格. 图中英文字母“NO GO”或“Z”: 表示螺纹塞规的止端。 螺纹塞规

4、检验工件时旋转螺纹规不能用力拧,用三只手指自然顺畅地旋转,止住即可,螺纹规退 出工件最后一圈时也要自然退出,不能用力拔出螺纹规,否则会影响产品检验结果的误差,螺纹规的损坏。 图4 图5 如上图4操作方法是正确的,图5是错误的,无需手握。 5、使用完毕后,及时清理干净螺纹规的通端(止端)的表面附着物,并存放在工具柜的量 具盒内。 四、注意事项 1、被测件螺纹公差等级及偏差代号必须与塞规标识公差等级、偏差代号相同,才可使用。 2、只有当通规和止规联合使用,并分别检验合格,才表示被测螺纹合格。 3、应避免与坚硬物品相互碰撞,轻拿轻放,以防止磕碰而损坏测量表面。 4、严禁将螺纹规作为切削工具强制旋入螺纹,避免造成早期磨损。 5、螺纹规使用完毕后,应及时清理干净测量部位附着物,存放在规定的量具盒内。 五、维护和保养 1、每月定期涂抹防锈油,以保证表面无锈蚀、无杂质(我们的螺纹规使用频繁且所 处环境干净无需上油保护)。 2、所有的螺纹规必须经计量校验机构校验合格后并在校验有效期内,方可使用。 3、损坏或报废的螺纹规应及时反馈处理,不得继续使用。 4、经校对的螺纹规计量超差或者达到计量器具周检期的螺纹规,由计量管理人员收回 并做相应的处理。

相关文档
最新文档