民法的人文关怀_英文_王利明

民法的人文关怀_英文_王利明
民法的人文关怀_英文_王利明

Social Sciences in China

V ol. XXXIII, No. 3, August 2012, 46-66

C ivil Law: Its Humanistic Concerns

Wang Liming

School of Law, Renmin University of China

比照近代民法以财产法为中心,现代民法强化了人文关怀,主要表现为从以财产法为中心到人法地位的提升,并广泛体现于民法中主体制度的发展、人格权的勃兴、

合同制度的发展、物权法的发展、侵权法的发展、婚姻家庭法的发展等各个方面。中

国未来的民法典应当以人文关怀构建价值理念,注重对人的自由和尊严的充分保障以

及对弱势群体的特殊关爱。基于这一理念,在中国未来民法典中有必要增加人格权法

和侵权责任法编。在中国民法的适用等方面更应强化人文关怀。

关键词:人文关怀民法典价值理念人格尊严

In contrast to early modern civil law, which centered on property law, modern civil

law shows intensi? ed humanistic concerns. This is mainly re? ected in the rising status of

personal law, and is also widely evidenced in the development within civil law of the subject,

personal rights, the contract system, real right law and tort law, as well as marriage and

family law. China’s future civil code should construct civil law values based on humanistic

concerns and highlight the full protection of human freedom and dignity and special care for

disadvantaged groups. In line with this idea, it is necessary to include law on personal rights

and tort law in the future civil code. Humanistic concerns should be strengthened in the

application of civil law.

Keywords: humanistic concerns, civil law code, values, personal dignity

Civil law, the basic law of civil society, also provides the basic regulation for the protection of private rights. At present, in this key period in the formulation of China’s civil code, it is especially important to stress the necessity of making the code adhere to realities and be oriented toward the future. It should not limit itself to focusing on the design of specific systems and regulations, but should be concerned with the values thereof. “By virtue of its abstract concepts and systems, the image of classical civil law became that of a self-contained system of scholarship from which one grasps with dif? culty the modern image of

ISSN 0252-9203

? 2012 Social Sciences in China Press

DOI: https://www.360docs.net/doc/d714017343.html,/10.1080/02529203.2012.702941

https://www.360docs.net/doc/d714017343.html,

Wang Liming47

civil law.”1 Studies of civil law cannot be con? ned to its external system or logical relations, but should rather set out from its values and, through historical investigation, gain an accurate grasp of its tendencies, so as to base it on a more scienti? c and more complete value system. With the values of the humanistic concerns of civil law as its basis, the present paper endeavors to expound its implications and its weighty in? uence on the improvement of the institutions and system of civil law.

I.Humanistic Concerns of Civil Law: From Centering on Property Law to Elevating the Status of Human Law

In early modern civil codes, relationships of property ownership and exchange formed the main subject of civil law norms. The centrality of property rights found expression chie? y in the control of external wealth; the law clearly neglected the spiritual dimension of human existence and simply materialized the diverse connotations of humanity.2 In this context, the value of man’s personal existence independent of property was far from clear. This constitutes the background of the Jhering’s famous proposition: “He who encroaches upon the property of a person encroaches also upon that person’s human dignity.”3

In terms of the historical development of civil law, it was the Jus Ro m anum that took the lead in adopting an abstract approach to developing and stipulating the abstract relations of private property,4 to lay down a system of independent personal right, obligation and real right and set out a whole system of private law. In this system, the exchange and ownership of property was the focus of readjustment; while there were regulations on personhood, the focus was more on “status” laws relating to eligibility for rights, which differed in meaning from the personal rights of modern law. Under the Jus Romanum, persona was used only to indicate a certain status.5 With the advent of the Middle Ages, the Jus Privatum system was found to be totally at loggerheads with canon law and the feudal land system and relations of dependency, so the Jus Romanum fell into a long silence. This lasted until the ? nal years of the Middle Ages, when the development of a commodity economy along the Mediterranean coast made property transactions more and more complex, providing a foundation for the revival of the Jus Romanum and at the same time meeting the needs of the Europe of a later day when the seeds of capitalism sprouted.

In the era of legal codi? cation, civil law, represented by the French Civil Code, aimed to eliminate feudal society’s oppression of man, oppose feudal trade barriers and encourage the development of a market economy. The French Civil Code adopted a three-part model

1 Kitagawa Zentaro, The Civil Law System of Japan, p. 115.

2 Xue Jun, “The Protection of the Person: The Basic Value in Drawing Up the Chinese Civil Code.”

3 Rudolf von Jhering, The Struggle for Law, p. 21.

4 Karl Marx, “Critique of Hegel’s Philosophy of Right,” p. 280.

5 Zhou Nan, On the Jus Romanum, p. 106.

48Social Sciences in China

consisting of statuta personalia, statuta realia, and ways to obtain property rights. Design of the statuta personalia focused in the main on the af? rmation of equality among men and ascertaining the ownership of property; as a result, property rights remained the core of the code as a whole,6 as was noted by the French scholar Savadi e r: “In contrast to laws having to do with persons, the (French) Civil Code bestowed the dominant position to laws having to do with property.”7

This property-centered character underwent little change in the German Civil Code. While in structure it adopted a ? ve-part model (General Principles, Right of Obligation, Real Right, Kinship and Inheritance), its core remained the sections on Right of Obligation and Real Right, and stipulations on the subject in the chapter on General Principles continued to center on the ownership and transactions of property. In the formulation of the German Civil Code, little importance was assigned to protecting the dignity of the individual. The law’s de? nition of the natural person was too simple and overlooked quite a few important rights of the person.8 Also, in terms of tort liability, the Civil Code limited its consideration to damages and treated them under the law of obligation, while imposing a rather strict limit on compensation for psychological damage. Not long after its proclamation, the German scholar Werner Sombart (1863-1941) noted its bias in “giving precedence to property rather than man.” As the Code’s very system had been designed to meet the demands of the commercial capitalist class, little wonder that it embodied that principle of “giving precedence to property rather than man” peculiar to the bourgeois class. Laws on the legal status and legal relations of the person yielded to laws on property.9 The very absence of the rights of the person in the German Civil Code was why, after WWII, German courts had to resort to the clauses on basic rights in the country’s constitution, instead of its legal code, to develop the rights of the person in general. This re? ected the fact that the German Civil Code had not given law on the rights of the person the status it should have had.10

The fact that the civil codes of the early modern period should have come to center on property law, or display what one might call a “pan-property” tendency,11 was due not only to the in? uence of the traditional civil law system but also, in particular, to their close relations with the socio-economic circumstances of their age. Both in its free and monopolistic stages, capitalism was characterized by the expansion of investment and encouragement of the creation of wealth, and the law, including civil law as a whole, had to serve this goal.12 Given the socio-economic background of the times, this practice was hardly inappropriate. Today,

6 Xie Huaishi, “Studies in the Civil Codes of Continental Law Countries.”

7 Eiichi Hoshino, Man in Private Law, p. 29.

8 Dieter Medicus, Allgemeiner Teil des BGB, p. 25.

9 Dieter Schwab, Einführung in das Zivilrecht, p. 31.

10 Xue Jun, “Exposing ‘General Human Rights’—Also on ‘System Consciousness’ in the Study of Comparative Jurisprudence.”

11 Xue Jun, “The Protection of the Person: The Basic Value in Drawing Up the Chinese Civil Code.”12 Max Weber, C ollected Works of Weber, vol. IV: Economy and Society, pp. 37-39.

Wang Liming49

with the development of the market economy and the advance of science and technology, weighty changes have occurred in the socio-economic pattern, so it is but natural that the development of civil law should present an increasing inclination toward humanistic concerns. By humanistic concerns is meant full protection of the freedom and dignity of man and special concern for disadvantaged social groups, with an emphasis on the protection of the person, which is taken to be the value basis of civil code.13 The present paper holds that “protection of the person” does not constitute an end in itself; rather, it is but a means to realize humanistic concerns whose ultimate goal is the achievement of human freedom and dignity. “The person” here refers, on the one hand, to the individual and his free pursuits, treated concretely and historically; on the other hand, it refers also to the person of ethics, whose dignity should be respected and whose basic personal interests should be protected. Humanistic concerns means, in this sense, making “man’s enjoyment of a decent existence” the goal of law and realizing what Marx called “the all-round emancipation of man.”

With their deep social and historical roots, the humanistic concerns of civil law are hardly an invention of the contemporary age. In ancient Greece, the sophist Protagoras proposed that “Man is the measure of all things”; in ancient Rome, such systems as personal law, private wrongs, etc., did display some degree of concern for everyone except slaves, even if they fell short of the all-round physical and personal protection provided by modern law. Of course, man had to wait till the Renaissance for the ? rst real emergence of humanist ideas, while it was the thinkers of the Enlightenment who further enriched the humanist connotations of early modern civil law. For example, the ideas of human rights, freedom, equality, etc., advocated by such thinkers as V oltaire and Montesquieu greatly helped the formation of such concepts as equality of persons, freedom of contract, autonomy of private law, etc., in early modern civil law. By this time, the basic framework of humanism had already taken shape in capitalist civil law. The fundamental characteristic of humanism lies in its focus on man himself, stressing his dignity and his spiritual freedom.14 Humanism holds that “the individual human being has a value in him or herself—we still use the Renaissance phrase, ‘the dignity of man’—and that it is respect for this which is the source of all other values and of human rights.”15

From the latter half of the 18th century, Kant’s philosophy of reason began to make a significant contribution to the establishment of the status of man as subject, holding that the absolute value of mankind lies in the dignity of man, with all human capacities as its basis: that man is an end in himself, not a means, and can only be taken as the end, not as the means.16 This means, according to Li Zehou: “Kant stresses here that while things have a monetary worth, man has only his inner worth; one cannot place a price on him for being useful to somebody. As a part of nature, man is hardly superior to an animal nor more

13 Xue Jun, “The Protection of the Person: The Basic Value in Drawing Up the Chinese Civil Code.”14 Meng Guanglin, A History of the Renaissance in Europe: Philosophy, p. 27.

15 Alan Bullock, The Humanist Tradition in the West, p. 234.

16 Immanuel Kant, Anthropology from a Pragmatic Point of View, p. 4.

50Social Sciences in China

valuable; but when he exists as noumenon and as the subject of practical reason (morality), he transcends all price.”17 It can be seen that the rise of the philosophy of reason made protection of the independence and dignity of the person into the core mission of society and, going further, the goal of the law as a whole. Once such beliefs had been established by the humanist movement, people came to believe that law could be constructed on the basis of reason. This was the impetus for legal reform, quickening the alliance between reason and civil law and bringing about the of? cial codi? cation of the law. The civil law codes of France, of Germany, of Austria, etc., were all products of enlightenment thought, embodying the humanistic spirit to some degree.18 In terms of values, the hierarchical ideas of feudal law were replaced by the humanistic ideas inherent in early modern civil law, while the hierarchical feudal system was replaced by the independence and equality of persons. However, compared with the values of humanistic concern advocated in this paper, it is clear that the philosophy of reason represented by Kant neglected the differences among men with regard to ability, intelligence, wealth, etc., and especially with regard to the special protection society provides for the disadvantaged, even though it did focus on the universal protection of man’s freedom.19 Hence there is a fairly large gap between the humanism of those days and the humanistic concerns of today.

After WWII and, in particular, in recent decades, the connotations of humanistic concern in civil law grew ever more plentiful and its status ever more apparent. This can be seen not only in the concrete institutions of civil law but also in the profound in? uence these concerns exert on the external system of civil law as a whole.20 In the ? rst place, respect for and protection of the person was raised to unprecedented heights and the human rights movement spread vigorously throughout the world. Correspondingly, man’s dignity and self-respect and his pursuit of a high-quality material and spiritual life found their full expression in civil law. The inhuman acts that took place on a wide scale during WWII and the revulsion they evoked after the war, as well as the human rights movement that began in the 1960s, all helped to promote and strengthen modern civil law’s concern for human dignity and respect. For example, the very ? rst article in the Basic Law of the Federal Republic of Germany declares that “the dignity of man is inviolable,” thus making “the dignity of man” a fundamental provision of the Basic Law. With the advent of the 21st century, respect and protection for human rights have become a universal consensus throughout international society. In the second place, industrialization and marketization have resulted in ever widening social polarization. A tiny minority of people have come to possess the lion’s share of the world’s wealth, while the phenomena of social inequality and injustice are becoming ever more striking. In these circumstances, the traditional view that freedom of contract would lead

17 Li Zehou, A Critique of Critical Philosophy, p. 290.

18 Alan Watson, The Making of the Civil Law, p. 144.

19 Stamatios Tzitzis, Qu’est-ce que la personne?, p. 84.

20 Zhu Yan, “Transformation of the Social Foundation and Construction of a Dual System of Civil Law.”

Wang Liming51

directly to social justice has become totally divorced from reality. On the contrary, the abuse of private property, manipulation of formal contracts by big business, the powerful position of monopolies in given fields, etc., have created all kinds of social injustice. This raises profound questions about people’s deep-rooted faith in the rationality of the property rights provided in civil law. Should modern civil law fail to be supplemented with the values of profound humanistic concern, this will result in further social injustice. In the third place, the rapid and vigorous development of modern science and technology has placed new demands on humanistic concerns with regard to civil law, acting as a new motive force for their development. Development of gene technology has made the protection of individual privacy all the more urgent and the emergence of test-tube babies has changed the traditional concept of life, while techniques for the production of arti? cial organs, stem cell research and development of cloning and tissue engineering have paved the way for mankind to ultimately solve the question of sources of human organs. At the same time, the science and technologies mentioned above pose new challenges to life, the body, health and other rights of the person, with the growing possibility of infringement of civil rights (especially the rights of the person) with ever more serious consequences; hence civil law needs to provide further protection. In the fourth place, following the fundamental satisfaction of man’s basic material needs, his spiritual needs grow more prominent. According to Maslow’s theory, man’s needs fall into ? ve categories. These are, from the lower to the higher level: physiological needs; need for security; need for social relationships; need for esteem; and need for self-actualization. Once people’s survival needs are fundamentally met, their cultural and spiritual needs grow stronger, something which Maslow summed up as the need for self-respect.21 Undoubtedly, the challenges these social changes pose for civil/commercial law are revolutionary. Against such a background, the revision and complementation of the traditional system of civil law with the profound value ideas of humanistic concern is indispensable.

After 1949, when China achieved “the people as masters of the country,” the value of man was accorded full respect and was fully expressed. However, owing to the prevalence of “leftist” ideology for quite some time and with the weakening of the idea of the rule of law, the idea of human-centered values was eroded for a while. After reform and opening up in 1978, the Party summed up and absorbed the tragic lessons of the “Cultural Revolution” and strengthened the construction of democracy and the system of law. With the deepening of reform and opening up, the socialist market economy system gradually came into existence. Striving for the great goal of a well-to-do and harmonious society, the Party and state have set up “taking people as the basis” as the governing idea. In terms of civil law, this means fully protecting the various rights and interests of citizens and respecting and defending their independence and dignity, making it possible for them to live with freedom and dignity. Consequently, the spirit of humanistic concerns embodied in our civil law differs in essence

21 Abraham H. Maslow, Motivation and Personality, pp. 40-54.

52Social Sciences in China

from the humanism of the West; it is the concentrated expression of the core values of socialism and is adapted to the social, economic and cultural development of our country at the present stage. It especially stresses a deep concern for disadvantaged groups, setting a full value on the freedom and development of the individual and striving to realize social equality and justice.

During the three decades and more of reform and opening up, the General Principles of Civil Law of 1986 and the series of laws promulgated in the years that followed laid down the regulations governing the ownership and exchange of property as well as the framework of civil/commercial law indispensable to the development of China’s market economy, greatly facilitating the country’s socio-economic development. However, against the background of our considerable achievements in socio-economic construction, our needs with regard to civil law cannot be limited only to the law’s economic function, but must have an even greater focus on its significant role in realizing humanistic concerns. On the one hand, interest relations multiply along with the rapid development and drastic transformation of society and social contradictions become ever more prominent, so that emphasis on the values of humanistic concern helps realize the goal of constructing a harmonious society. On the other hand, the all-round emancipation and development of man constitutes the basic purpose of socialism and of the construction of a country ruled by law, as well as the construction of a harmonious society. The socialist legal system that has been established so far embodies the value orientation of humanistic concerns in an all-round way. Compared with other departments of law, the humanistic concerns displayed by civil law are even more comprehensive and more focused on harmonizing the conflict between different interests. Emphasis on the humanistic concerns of civil law takes the happiness and dignity of the individual as the ultimate end of state and society, not as the means for realizing other purposes. Modernization does not mean simple economic modernization; rather, it is the modernization of man himself that counts. In a certain sense, civil law can also be called human law; modern civil law, the most important legal form for protecting the all-round development of man, can never be divorced from the protection of humanistic values.

II.Constructing the Value Ideas of Civil Law with Humanistic Concerns

Even though traditional civil law did take freedom and equality as its basic value orientation, these values have to be subjected to certain readjustments and changes under the impact of modern society’s value ideas of humanistic concerns. This is because traditional civil law was designed around property rights. Thus considerations of the values of humanistic concern are gradually becoming the basic value system of civil law at the same time as the positive elements of traditional values are carried on.

1. Full protection for the freedom and dignity of man

Freedom in terms of civil law differs from freedom at the economic level; its core is

Wang Liming53

respect for the subject’s self-determination at the level of personal dignity. For civil law, human dignity constitutes an inalienable and irrepressible value, the fundamental condition that determines what makes a man human. With the advent of the 21st century, respect for and protection of human rights has become a universal consensus in international society .

On the one hand, an emphasis on the freedom and dignity of man has found concentrated expression in laws on personal rights. Article One of the Universal Declaration of Human Rights stipulates that “All human beings are born free and equal in dignity and rights,” and Article Three that “Everyone has the right to life, liberty and security of person.” Article Two of the 1948 Basic Law of the Federal Republic of Germany provides in clear terms for the “protection of the free development of the human person,” and it was on the principle of “the inviolability of human dignity” set up by that article that German judges developed personal rights in general, embodying in private law the values of the protection of human dignity and the free development of the individual and protecting privacy and other rights or interests by means of the system of general personal rights.22 In recent decades, various countries have given further attention to strengthening the protection of personal interests and improving the way in which such protection is provided for when drawing up new civil codes or revising and “re-codifying” their civil law codes; this can be seen from the newly proclaimed civil law codes of a number of countries. Many of these codes devote several articles to the protection of personal rights, expanding the way in which such protection is to be applied and strengthening the protection of personal interests in their sections on family law and other areas. The interests of the human person are becoming ever more prominent and are gaining pride of place in civil rights.23

On the other hand, the idea of affording full protection to human freedom and dignity is being comprehensively provided for in the various speci? c systems represented in the law of torts. In traditional civil law, from Jus Romanum to the German Civil Code, compensation for damages revolves around property, stressing payment in property while neglecting compensation for mental harm. Thus the gradual recognition since the 20th century of compensation for mental harm indicates to a certain degree the broadening of respect for human dignity. Furthermore, in the system of protection of rights and interests under civil law, such rights and interests have different degrees of precedence, with personal dignity and freedom always coming first. In particular, the life, health and interests of the person enjoy strengthened protection. With regard to the reducibility of rights, the right to property is reducible in principle, but the reduction of personal rights calls for caution. Some rights, such as the right to life and health are simply irreducible. The law of torts broadens the scope of rights to be protected by civil law. Throughout the whole process, personal rights, especially the non-contractual protection of human dignity, has taken pride of place. As one

22 Karl Larenz, Allgemeiner Teil des Deutschen Bürgerlichen Rechts,vol. 1, p. 170.

23 Charlotte Girard and Armand Henneuse, La dignité de la personne humaine: recherche sur un processus de juridicisation, p. 87.

54Social Sciences in China

of the basic values of Western democracy, personal dignity has, at present, been gradually established through judicial precedents and written legislation as a right under private law, any infringement upon which quali? es the victim to sue directly for remedy.24

It is because the law of personal rights and tort law embody concern for and protection of man that these two departments of civil law have become growth points for the theory and system of modern civil law.

2. Special solicitude for the disadvantaged

Taking as its basis man’s personal dignity in the abstract, civil law has since early modern times stressed equality in the formal sense, assuming men to be “equal” and “interchangeable.”25 Against such a background, civil law took as its object the readjustment of property and personal relations between equal subjects, disregarding in principle the differences among these subjects in terms of age, sex, race, economic power, knowledge, etc., and holding them to be of equal status. It also held not only that each should enjoy basic rights, but also that those rights should be equal among persons; only in this way would a harmonious society be possible.26 The equality that 19th century civil law sought was formal equality, which found expression in recognition of the equality of the civil rights capacity of all natural persons under the civil code. What is termed the move “from status to contract” actually meant the process of pursuing formal equality. Formal equality concerns itself, in the sphere of contract law, only with the parties’ equality in the abstract, without paying too much attention to whether they are equal in their negotiation capacities. Similarly, in the ? eld of real right, civil law stipulates an abstract equality with regard to quali? cations for acquisition of property and protection of property ownership, but places little stress on the distribution of property or concern for the disadvantaged. Though this formal equality has so far remained the basic value of civil law, an increasing number of factors relating to substantive equality have been injected into civil law since the beginning of the 20th century on the basis of value considerations relating to the protection of social equality and justice, the need to protect the security and order of transactions, etc. This has found expression not only in a major increase in content relating to substantive equality with the gradual formation of areas of law separate from the civil code in the ? elds of labor protection, consumer rights, workplace injury insurance, etc., but also, in some countries, in the addition to the traditional civil code of contents relating to substantive justice, so as to adapt to society’s changing demands. For example, one may cite the provision for a period in which goods can be returned without any reason and other special regulations on the cancellation of contracts dealing with certain transactions in consumer goods, added to the German Civil Code after the passage of the Act on Modernization of the Law of Obligations.

24 For the development of provisions on human dignity in Western legal systems, see C. McCrudden, “Human Dignity and Judicial Interpretation of Human Rights,” pp. 655, 667.

25 Liang Huixing, ed., Civil Law from the Early Modern to the Modern Era, pp. 169-170.

26 Wang Haiming, “Equality: A New Discussion.”

Wang Liming55

Without protection of the disadvantaged, substantive justice cannot be truly realized. The research findings of Wilkinson and other British scholars show that countries that stress equality are better off than their counterparts with too great a gap between rich and poor, whether in the quality of their economic growth, their social stability, indices of the happiness of their inhabitants, or their crime rate.27 This is of course of great significance for civil legislation. Montesquieu put it well: “It is here that civil law ought to triumph, which, with the eyes of a mother, regards every individual as the whole community.”28 Very clearly do these words express the idea that although civil law practices formal equality, it can never exclude substantive equality. What is more, substantive justice has to be stressed if the normal order of the market economy is to be sustained, as the subjects of market transactions are concrete persons, not abstract ones. Formal equality is universal and reflects basic human needs, but it is inadequate in that differences in negotiation capacity, economic power, etc., among the parties in real life transactions work to the advantage of those with economic and social superiority, giving them an advantage in the gaming process so that they gain greater bene? ts than the weak. Thus if formal equality alone is pursued, the value system of civil law will rigidify and instead of embodying concern and care for the disadvantaged, it will harm equality and justice, resulting in substantive inequality.29

Care and concern for the disadvantaged does not, of course, mean negating formal justice, but rather making up to a certain extent for its inadequacies. Rather than being the main goal to be pursued, substantive equality can only be a concurrent subject of attention for our future civil code. Since encouragement of competition and promotion of innovation are important guarantees for social progress, the emphasis on substantive equality in civil law and indeed in other social law has to be con? ned within a given scope, otherwise it will con? ict with the inherent substance of civil law. The reason that laws covering labor, protection of consumers’ rights, etc., have been separated from civil law in recent years is to be found, to a large extent, in civil law’s emphasis on formal equality and the abstract person, whereas these other laws mainly stress substantive equality and the concrete person. Thus substantive equality has to be realized mainly through laws other than civil law, especially social law. However, to use humanistic concerns to construct value ideas for civil law does not mean any negation of those civil law values that center on the autonomy of the will. Humanistic concerns do not negate the civil subject’s autonomy of will in a transaction; on the contrary, to a certain degree they help to make up for possible inadequacies in the concrete civil subject’s autonomy of will and to attain a fuller realization of that autonomous will. Autonomy of the will means autonomy of private law and refers to the fact that the party concerned has the right, within the bounds of private law, to decide freely on his actions and determine his mode of communication

27 Richard Wilkinson and Kate Pickett, The Spirit Level: Why Greater Equality Makes Societies Stronger, 2009.

28 Charles-Louis Montesquieu, The Spirit of the Laws, p. 190.

29 “Allow the Peasants to Enjoy a Reasonable Premium from Their Collective Land,” p. 2.

56Social Sciences in China

when participating in civil life without being subjected to illegal interference.30 Through the autonomy of private law, civil law makes it possible for the individual to enjoy a freedom that is protected by law and to make autonomous decisions; therein lies its advantage.31 However, autonomy of the will is not without its own defects. On the one hand, overemphasis on autonomy of the will may be accompanied by a whole series of social problems, such as abuse of proprietary rights, intensi? ed economic monopoly, environmental pollution, etc. It will not lead naturally either to social justice or to social harmony, and so should be curbed. These restraints are usually provided by state intervention. On the other hand, while it constitutes the basis of freedom of action, the core of autonomy of the will lies in the disposition of property; it does not generally extend to the sphere of the person. The freedom found in autonomy of the will is, in the main, the freedom of economic disposition, which differs signi? cantly from the freedom attached to personal rights. For example, in the disposition of the likeness of an individual, individual privacy, personal data, etc., the emphasis should be on respect and protection for the individual’s right of self-determination, which constitutes an inalienable part of the individual person and may not, on principle, be “freely” disposed of. Over-emphasizing the autonomy of the will may well lead to dealing with personal interests as a type of transaction. Once the idea of humanistic concern is introduced, the ? rst thing to do is to establish the legal principle of the precedence of the protection of life and health over autonomy of the will, so that any transaction based on autonomy of the will that infringes on personal dignity and freedom is automatically annulled. Seen in this light, the position of humanistic concerns should be over and above that of autonomy of the will.32 This does not, however, in any sense imply abandonment of autonomy of the will, but rather compensates for its inability to fully ensure respect and protection of the human person.

Full protection for man’s freedom and dignity together with concern and care for disadvantaged groups constitute the core contents of civil law’s humanistic concerns. The general orientation of our civil code in the future will lie in strengthening its concern for man while maintaining the principle of the autonomy of the will, so as to make up for the inadequacies inherent in the latter. Of necessity, a civil code that takes as its fundamental legislative mission “to care for man, nurture man, and make him all he can be” will reflect the all-round development of man, which will find expression not only in the all-round enhancement and protection of man’s subjective attributes and in emphasizing and safeguarding all his rights, but also in the all-round realization of his freedom. Whether or not our future civil code re? ects man as subject will decide, to a considerable extent, whether it is scienti? c and reasonable. Only a civil code that cares for the individual can be vital, of high quality, and supported and followed by the people. Not only should each person enjoy basic rights; these rights should also be equal. Only in this way will it be possible to construct a

30 Su Haopeng, “Civil Law Culture: An Initial Theoretical Analysis.”

31 Dieter Medicus, Allgemeiner Teil des BGB, p. 143.

32 Basil S. Markesinis, Foreign Law and Comparative Methodology: A Subject and a Thesis, p. 235.

Wang Liming57 society of harmony.33

III.Constructing a Civil Law System Using the Idea of Humanistic Concerns

Civil law consists of an internal and an external system. The latter, the aussere Systematik, refers to such formal systems as the structure of compilation, while the former, the innere Systematik, stands for the value system of civil law, covering its values, principles, etc.34 In terms of the external system, whether it be the three-chapter system of the French or the ? ve-chapter system of Germany, the system has traditionally mainly been constructed with property law at its center. The right elaborated in the ideas on private law of Christian Wolff, the leading ? gure of the Pandekten School, where he speaks of the centrality of civil rights in civil law, refers in the main to property rights. Wolff’s discussion carries on the Renaissance tradition of liberal jurisprudence; setting out from the theory of natural law, expounds civil rights’ central place in civil law and de? nes the essence of human action as obligation (obligatio). The rights he discusses are, however, mainly property rights. From the perspective of the German Civil Code, civil rights typically means nothing other than real right, right of obligation and right of inheritance, so it follows that its stress on the central position of rights actually means the central position of property rights. While the general principles of the Pandekten School fail to give personal law any prominence, the three-chapter model of France does so. “By comparison, Roman law is more rational,” said Mei Zhongxie, comparing the merits and demerits of the two civil codes of France and Germany. “Since everyone has a mother and even a beggar may have a wife, assigning kinship law the ? rst place in civil law not only ? ts well with the principles of natural law, but also avoids the suspicion of putting property above people.”35 But even these codes did not give prominence, either in their contents or in their speci? c systems, to the protection of the freedom and dignity of man. The three-chapter format itself came from the Gaii Institutionum Commentarii IV of Gaius: “Omne autem ius quo utimur vel ad personas pertinet, vel ad res, vel ad actiones (Every right which we enjoy concerns either persons, things or actions).” Obviously, ‘person’ in Roman personal law differs greatly from what we mean by the same word, as has been pointed out by Xue Jun: “As a whole, the system of ‘personal law’ of the Jus Romanum is a system of unequal status, of hierarchy. We cannot require the ancients to live up to our modern standards”;36 nor can we expect people in the age of slavery to have been concerned with issues like human dignity and equality. Besides, what was mainly de? ned in the personal law of the three-chapter format of the French civil code was the subject system; systems of personal rights were not seen as an important element for standardization. Traditional civil law took the transaction as its central element and served essentially for

33 Wang Haiming, “Equality: A New Discussion.”

34 Franz Bydlinski, System und Prinzipien des Privatrechts, p. 48ff.

35 Mei Zhongxie, Essentials of Civil Law, p. 18.

36 Xue Jun, “The Distance between Ideal and Reality,” p. 195.

58Social Sciences in China

exchange and for the creation of wealth. The subject entity it af? rmed was in the main the subject in the exchange. “Capacity of disposition” here means in essence capacity to undertake a transaction, the absence of which would chie? y affect the conduct of the transaction. The key to the system of real right in civil law was that it served to provide transactions with their premise and basis and also guaranteed their outcomes. Besides, what civil law af? rmed was property ownership, whereas the law of obligation af? rmed property transactions. The system of legal action, as an instrument of the autonomy of private law, was chie? y concerned with the autonomy of private law in the field of property and was, in essence, in the service of the will of the actor himself. It was in this sense that the system of civil law was regarded, not without reason, as having expanded and developed with property rights at its center. It is not unreasonable for scholars to criticize the valuation of things above people; however, to consider this as an orientation towards people versus an orientation towards property would be too extreme.37 One needs to see the connection between the state of the law and the historical background of the times; law has to serve the social demands of its age.

Theoretically, the internal and external systems of civil law are independent of and different from each other: the internal system is the basis on which the external system comes into shape, and its changes necessarily extend and spread into the external system. Also, people tend to separate the value system from the external system, yet the two cannot be isolated from one other. On the basis of the fact that humanistic concerns have become an indispensable value for our system of civil law, that system’s external form should adapt to the values of humanistic concerns, so as to make the civil code respond in full to society’s demands, energized by the fresh breath of the times. Especially, with tort acts and the right to human dignity becoming the new growth points of civil law, the value ideas of humanistic concerns have gained further prominence. Changes in these value concepts will necessarily lead to the development of our system of civil law and the re-reading of the existing system. To respond to the idea of humanistic concerns, civil law should, in the ? rst place, single out personal right and make it an independent chapter in the civil code, offering a protection that will make up for the inadequacy of the system with regard to the human person. It is the law of personal right that embodies, in civil law as a whole, the most direct and comprehensive respect for and protection of man. The suggestion that personal right be made an independent chapter is aimed at developing a complete content and system for this area. In the traditional system of civil rights, no independent personal rights stand on a par with property rights; civil rights centered on property rights, and it was on the basis of the protection of property rights that the system of civil law was constructed. However, with the progress of social and economic development and the growing importance of the protection of human rights, the fetishism that summed up man’s very existence as a matter of property rights has become obsolete; increasing value is set on the individual’s spiritual rights, on the value of his feelings and sensations to his existence, and on the damage in? icted by spiritual trauma and pain to his

37 Xu Guodong, “New Humanism and Civil Law Theory in China.”

Wang Liming59

interests as a person.38 As a result, personal rights are taking an ever more prominent place in the civil law of today, with their own system of rights and institutions vis-à-vis property rights. It can even be said that modern civil law gives more importance to the protection of personal rights than to the protection of property rights.39 The high pro? le of personal rights has had a great in? uence on the whole civil law system, leading civil law jurists to give consideration to its reconstruction.40 Obviously, making personal rights an independent chapter ? ts in well with the basic value of humanistic concern. Another category of rights running parallel with property rights in civil law is rights of the person, which covers personality rights. Rights of the person and property rights constitute the two basic categories of right in civil law, and the systems de? ning them are the mainstay of civil law. Other civil rights are either covered under these two categories or are the product of their union, such as intellectual property rights, inheritance rights, etc. Should personal rights fail to become an independent chapter, it will be very dif? cult for intellectual property rights and other rights that contain personality rights to occupy their due place in the civil code. As the attributes of different rights form the basic standard for distinguishing one chapter of the civil law system from another, for personal rights to be made an independent chapter simply ful? lls the inherent requirement of the logic and the systematic nature of legal codes. The fact that the 1986 General Principles of Civil Law was so well received at home and abroad and applauded as a declaration of rights was due, to a very great extent, to its listing of various civil rights including personal rights, an occurrence that was of epoch-making signi? cance. The very elucidation of basic personal rights—what makes man human—provided civil subjects with a legal weapon to fight all actions infringing upon their personal rights. After publication of the General Principles of Civil Law, people came to realize that wounding and killing were not only criminal offences, but also infringed upon the life and health of others who were entitled to a remedy in private law. For the ? rst time in many decades—even in thousands of years—people found that as individuals in society they had personality rights to things such as their reputation, image, etc. To create an independent personality rights chapter in the civil code, and to further af? rm and protect these rights in a comprehensive way, con? rming the civil subject’s right to the power to exclude unlawful interference and infringement by others and bestowing on all individuals the weapon to fight any illegal acts that would “look down on man, hold him in contempt and make him less than human”—will not only lead citizens to see their own values in a new light but will encourage them in all earnestness to respect the rights of others.41 This will necessarily have a powerful in? uence on the construction of democracy and the rule of law in this country.

38 Zhang Xiaojun, “Remedy and Objective Expansion of Compensation for Psychological Damage to Substantial Right of Personality ,” p. 617.

39 Shi Chunling, “Real Right’s Active Quest for and V oluntary Yielding to Personal Right.”

40 Wang Liming, “Status of the System of Personal Right in the Chinese Civil Code.”

41 Li Lihui, “A Tentative Discussion on Whether Personal Right Can Constitute an Independent Chapter of the Civil Code.”

60Social Sciences in China

Another change brought about in the civil law system by the introduction of the values of humanistic concern was the fact that tort law was made into an independent chapter. While the heated arguments thus touched off 42 seem to have settled down following the enactment and promulgation of the Tort Law of the PRC, academic circles have continued to question the rationality of separating tort law from the law of obligation. The problem, as this writer sees it, cannot be observed and understood at the formal level; rather, it has to be understood from the angle of humanistic concern. Modern civil law differs from traditional civil law in that it emphasizes not only the protection of property, but also the protection, and even preferential protection, of rights of the person. To strengthen protection of the victim, tort liability law in each country tends, on the whole, to develop from simple compensation for damage to multiple remedies. While the diversi? cation of tort liability does not alter tort law’s character as a law chie? y directed at compensation, it can lead to diverse forms of liability. Forms of liability that fall outside damages do not constitute relations of obligation. Making the law on tort liability an independent chapter helps provide the victim with a uni? ed means or way of remedy. In order to strengthen the victim’s remedy, tort law has set up comprehensive modes of remedy, such as links with insurance, social salvage, etc. All this shows that simply introducing tort law into the system of the law of obligation does not provide a way to include all of its contents. The alternative that remains is to make it an independent chapter; only thus can a full and thorough expression be found for tort law’s values in terms of humanistic concerns.

IV.Humanistic Concerns and the Future Orientation of Chinese Civil Law

With the Constitution of the PRC as the core and the law as the backbone, including such normative documents as administrative and local regulations and rules, we have built up, fundamentally, a legal system with Chinese characteristics comprising seven legal branches and three levels of legal norms; have constructed a basic legal framework for our market economy; and have protected the normal order of our social and economic life. At the level of legislation, however, we can see that while the main basic laws in the various legal branches have already been formulated, the fact that our civil code has not so far been ? nalized means that the task of integrating and perfecting our legal system remains an onerous one. To ensure that our legal system plays its due role in the development of our socialist market economy and democratic politics and the active construction of a harmonious society, we must explicitly elucidate the value orientation of the civil code and make it our guide in building a scienti? c, rational civil code that re? ects the spirit of the times. Clearly, then, we do not conduct discussions on the values of humanistic concerns out of a metaphysical academic preference, but with a view to the selection of values in our civil legislation and judicial

42 Wang Liming, “An Inevitable Split after a Long Time of Union: On the Relations between Tort Law and the Law of Obligation”; “On Tort Law’s Making Up an Independent Chapter.”

Wang Liming61

practice. In China, so long lacking in any tradition of civil law, existing civil legislation has been found insuf? cient to support the market economy even when a preliminary legal order has been established. At a time when both social and economic development have reached a new stage, how to renew our legal ideas and make them better adapted to developments in society, how to make civil law carry out its legal role more ef? ciently and how to make the legal system as a whole play its rightful part—this is the most urgent task we are faced with today.

Our country’s legal system is an open one; similarly, its civil law is also in a dynamic process of development, carrying out different historical missions and embodying different functions and attributes in different historical periods. From the perspective of China’s civil legislation process, we can see that the commodity economy theory proposed by Tong Rou in the initial days of reform and opening up was meant in the main to construct a comprehensive civil law system in terms of those functions of civil law that relate to relations of exchange. It was in such thinking that the basic framework and idea of the country’s civil law was grounded, with a logic based on the constant emphasis, in all civil codes from the Jus Romanum to those of the era of codi? cation, on the central place of property law and the law’s mission in standardizing property transactions. Its historic merit lies in making us truly aware of civil law’s function in the market; that is, the fact that civil law’s status as a law of equal subjects has to be established if the market economy is ever to be realized. At the same time, we must set up the basic rules of the market, i.e., the rules of civil law, including those on the subject entity and on the rights of ownership and obligation. As Tong Rou sees it, the advanced commodity economy constitutes a stage in the course of mankind’s development that cannot be bypassed. Accordingly, our civil law must shoulder the great mission of preserving order and promoting the development of the economy.43 This theory, an important innovation in civil jurisprudence, has laid the foundation for civil legislation in China. During the thirty years and more since reform and opening up, our country has covered a course of development that took the West several centuries to complete. One might say that this testi? es to the great merits of civil law in the commodity economy!

Following the establishment of the market economy in China, both marketization and industrialization have developed to the full. Our country has become the world’s second biggest economy, with considerable accumulation of material wealth and substantial improvements in people’s livelihood. Under these conditions, the task of civil legislation should not stop at laying down the basic foundation for a market economy; it must take on the higher goal of concern for man. Right now, the country is in a process of rapid transition; its sharpening social contradictions and ever-changing society make it hard to decide on institutional rules for the civil code.44 In the past three decades and more, interest patterns

43 Tong Rou and Wang Liming, “Development and Perfection of Chinese Civil Law in the Reform of the Economic System.”

44 Office of the Organizational Committee for “100 Lectures by 100 Jurisprudents,” A Hundred Schools on the Rule of Law, p. 444.

62Social Sciences in China

have become ever more complicated as social contradictions intensify, such as the con? icts that take place when land is requisitioned and houses demolished for reconstruction projects and the tensions to do with resources and the environment. The appropriate solution for all these problems requires that we return to man himself and think anew about how to realize man’s all-round development instead of the one-sided pursuit of GDP growth prevalent now throughout the country. Our legal system needs to respond to this reality of social transformation and, especially, to write a civil code with Chinese characteristics and Chinese style that faces up to the 21st century and holds a unique place among the civil codes of the world. Furthermore, to meet the needs of the country’s socio-economic development, we should introduce humanistic concerns; instead of sticking to the 19th century value system of the West as the ultimate truth, we must set out from the needs of the realities of China to emphasize humanistic concerns and strive for innovation and development in terms of our value system and formal system.

Our civil code of the future should be grounded in humanistic concerns. This requires, on the one hand, that we construct its value system in accordance with the needs of humanistic concerns. The code’s value rationality is ultimate concern for man. In terms of civil law’s ideas, besides strengthening the autonomy of the will, it is also necessary that man’s dignity and freedom should be given equal importance and that these values should run throughout the institutions and systems of the code. During the legislative process, full consideration should be given to the interests and claims of comparatively disadvantaged groups, providing them with the means of fully voicing their demands; their personal dignity must be respected and their lawful rights must be protected. On the other hand, we must adhere to the ideal of humanistic concern in structuring the external system of our civil law. As well as standardizing property rights and transactions, we should, while preserving the existing system of property rights, uphold humanistic concerns as the basis for institutional design by adding independent chapters on the system of personal rights and on tort liability. Humanistic concerns demand that we persist with the idea of justice and adhere to the principles of respect for and protection of the dignity of man. The law contains man’s spirit and his sense of justice; it is not the animal kingdom’s law of the jungle. Law is a secular game, and the rules of that game. Its task is to ensure that people’s acts are governed by rules; it is not a tool for winning obedience through coercion.45

Our emphasis on humanistic concerns does not imply the all-round transformation of civil law, nor a negation of its existing values and systems. The fact is, our civil law of today is not in a critical state, nor does it need to overcome a crisis of this kind. What our civil law needs is simply to add new value ideas to its existing value system to give it more vigor. Civil law simply inherits and further develops the past; it does not negate it. Looked at from the contemporary perspective, civil law in the 19th century did display a tendency to “place more value on things than on people,” but this ? tted in well with the situation in those days. Today,

45 Hou Jian and Lin Yanmei, Humanistic Trends in Jurisprudence, p. 28.

Wang Liming63

we need to adapt to changing social needs, developing the values of civil law and expanding its functions, so that our civil law will remain eternally youthful and vigorous.

We should make even greater efforts to ensure that the idea of taking man as the basis permeates the application of civil law. In areas of the judicial process where legal provisions are incomplete, the interpretation and application of the law in speci? c cases should always incline to the more disadvantaged party, so long as this does not contradict basic legal principles. Humanism as a theoretical system is highly logical and consistent; the humanities aim at giving full play to man’s potential, cultivating his character and perfecting him by means of humanist education.46 The legal person is not a tool making mechanical use of law articles, what he faces is real-life society in all its conflicts and contradictions, with their complex backgrounds and social sources. In this light, legal education must cultivate humanistic feelings and attitudes in students, so that they can more readily and more effectively resolve social conflicts and contradictions in their future work. The realization of humanistic concerns in legal education demands that we regard man from the perspective of man, rejecting both the mechanistic and the utilitarian pattern of thinking and refusing to simplify man. John Merryman has warned against excessively rigid application of the law: “The picture of the judicial process that emerges is one of fairly routine activity. The judge becomes a kind of expert clerk.”47 This in fact over-stresses legal formalism and conceptual jurisprudence, seeing it as nothing but the natural outgrowth of syllogism. In contrast, humanistic concerns always uphold the idea of justice throughout the whole process and maintain an attitude of respect for personal dignity. Law is both rational and emotional; it is a product of the will, yet it must be guided by justice.48 Humanistic concern is a sentiment judges must adhere to; it will bring them closer to the mass of the people, so that “The judiciary serves the people” does not remain a mere slogan, but is embodied in speci? c cases.

Notes on Contributor

Wang Liming, Ph.D. in Law, is Professor and Doctoral Supervisor of the School of Law, Renmin University of China. His main research interests are civil and commercial law. His representative works are: A Study of State Ownership (国家所有权研究, Beijing: China Renmin University Press, 1991), On Liability for Breach of Contract (违约责任论, revised version, Beijing: China University of Political Science and Law Press, 2000), Studies on the General Principles of Civil Law (民法总则研究, Beijing: China Renmin University Press, 2003), Studies on the Law of Personal Right (人格权法研究, Beijing: China Renmin University Press, 2005), Studies on the Law of Real Right (物权法研究, two volumes, Beijing: China Renmin University Press, 2007), Studies on the System of the Civil Code (民法典体系研究, Beijing: China Renmin University Press, 2008) and Studies on the Law of Liability for Tort (侵权责任法研究, two volumes, Beijing: China Renmin University Press, 2010). E-mail: wangliming@https://www.360docs.net/doc/d714017343.html,.

46 Ibid., p. 7.

47 John Henry Merryman, The Civil Law Tradition, p. 36.

48 Hou Jian and Lin Yanmei, Humanist Trends in Jurisprudence, p. 28.

64Social Sciences in China

References

“Allow the Peasants to Enjoy a Reasonable Premium from their Collective Land” (让农民享有集体土地合理溢价收益). The Beijing News (新京报), February 1, 2011.

Bullock, Alan. The Humanist Tradition in the West. Trans. Dong Leshan. Shanghai: Shanghai Joint Publishing Company, 1997.

Bydlinski, Franz. System und Prinzipien des Privatrechts. Wien/New York: Springer-Verlag, 1996. Girard, Charlotte and Armand Henneuse. La dignité de la personne humaine: recherche sur un processus de juridicisation. Paris: PUF, 2005.

Hoshino, Eiichi. Man in Private Law. Trans. Wang Chuang. Beijing: China Legal Publishing House, 2004.

Jhering, Rudolf von. The Struggle for Law. Trans. Zheng Yongliu. Beijing: Law Press · China, 2007. Kant, Immanuel. Anthropology from a Pragmatic Point of View. Trans. Deng Xiaomang. Chongqing: Chongqing Publishing House, 1987.

Kitagawa, Zentaro. Civil Law System of Japan. Trans. Li Yiduo and Qiu Jingchun. Beijing: Science Press, 1995.

Hou, Jian and Lin Yanmei. Humanistic Trends in Jurisprudence (人文主义法学思潮). Beijing: Law Press · China, 2007.

Larenz, Karl. Allgemeiner Teil des Deutschen Bürgerlichen Rechts,vol. 1. Trans. Wang Xiaoye et al. Beijing: Law Press · China, 2003.

Li, Lihui. “A Tentative Discussion on Whether Personal Right Can Constitute an Independent Chapter in the Civil Code” (浅议人格权在民法典中能否独立成编). Journal of Heilongjiang Administ r ative Cadre Institute of Politics and Law (黑龙江省政法管理干部学院学报), 2002, no. 3.

Li, Zehou. A Critique of Critical Philosophy (批判哲学的批判). Beijing: People’s Publishing House, 1979.

Liang, Huixing, ed. Civil Law from the Early Modern to the Modern Era (从近代民法到现代民法). Beijing: China Legal Publishing House, 2000.

Markesinis, Basil S. Foreign Law and Comparative Methodology: A Subject and a Thesis. Oxford: Hart Publishing, 1997.

Marx, Karl. “Critique of Hegel’s Philosophy of Right.” In Complete Works of Marx and Engels, vol. 1. Beijing: People’s Publishing House, 1956.

Maslow, Abraham Harold. Motivation and Personality. Trans. Xu Jinsheng and Cheng Zhaoxiang. Beijing: Huaxia Publishing House, 1987.

McCrudden, C. “Human Dignity and the Judicial Interpretation of Human Rights.” European Journal of International Law, vol. 19, 2008, no. 4.

Medicus, Dieter. Allgemeiner Teil des BGB. Trans. Shao Jiandong. Beijing: Law Press · China, 2000. Mei, Zhongxie. Essentials of Civil Law (民法要义). Beijing: China University of Political Science and Law Press, 1998.

Meng, Guanglin. A History of the Renaissance in Europe: Philosophy (欧洲文艺复兴史 [哲学卷]). Beijing: People’s Publishing House, 2008.

Wang Liming65

Merryman, John Henry. Civil Law Tradition. Trans. Gu Peidong and Lu Zhengping. Beijing: Law Press · China, 2004.

Montesquieu, Charles-Louis. The Spirit of the Laws. Trans. Zhang Yanshen. Beijing: The Commercial Press, 1997.

Of? ce of the Organizational Committee for “100 Lectures by 100 Jurists.” A Hundred School s on the Rule of Law (法治百家谈), vol. 1. Beijing: China Chang’an Publishing House, 2007.

Schwab, Dieter. Einführung in das Zivilrecht. Trans. Zheng Ch o ng. Beijing: Law Press · China, 2006. Shi, Chunling. “Real Right’s Active Quest for and V oluntary Yielding to Personal Right” (财产权对人格权的积极索取与主动避让). Hebei Law Science (河北法学), 2010, no. 9.

Su, Haopeng. “Civil Law Culture: An Initial Theoretical Analysis” (民法文化:一个初步的理论解析). Journal of Comparative Law (比较法研究), 1997, no. 3.

Tong, Rou and Wang Liming. “Development and Perfection of Chinese Civil Law in the Reform of the Economic System” (我国民法在经济体制改革中的发展与完善). China Legal Science (中国法学), 1985, no. 1.

Tzitzis, Stamatios. Qu’est-ce que la personne?. Paris: Armand Colin, 1999.

Wang, Haiming. “Equality: A New Discussion” (平等新论). Zhongguo Shehui Kexue (中国社会科学), 1998, no. 5.

Wang, Liming. “An Inevitable Split after a Long Time of Union: On the Relations between Tort Law and the Law of Obligation” (合久必分:侵权行为法与债法的关系). In Jurisprudence Frontline (法学前沿), vol. 1. Beijing: Law Press · China, 1997.

——. “On Tort Law’s Making Up an Independent Chapter” (论侵权行为法的独立成编). Modern Law Science (现代法学), 2003, no. 4.

——. “Status of the System of Personal Right in the Chinese Civil Code” (人格权制度在中国民法典中的地位). CASS Journal of Law (法学研究), 2003, no. 2.

Watson, Alan. The Making of Civil Law. Trans. Li Jingbing and Yao Xinhua. Beijing: China Legal Publishing House, 2005.

Weber, Max. Collected Works of Weber, vol. IV: Economy and Society. Trans. Kang Le et al. Guilin: Guangxi Normal University Press, 2004.

Wilkinson, Richard and Kate Pickett. The Spirit Level: Why Greater Equality Makes Societies Stronger. New York: Bloomsbury Press, 2009.

Xie, Huaishi. “Studies in the Civil Codes of Continental Law Countries” (大陆法国家民法典研究). Foreign Law Translation and Review (外国法译评), 1994, no. 3.

Xu, Guodong. “New Humanism and Civil Law Theory in China” (新人文主义与中国民法理论). Study & Exploration (学习与探索), 2006, no. 6.

Xue, Jun. “Exposing ‘General Human Rights’—Also on ‘System Consciousness’ in the Study of Comparative Jurisprudence” (揭开“一般人格权”的面纱——兼论比较法研究中的“体系意识”). Journal of Comparative Law (比较法研究), 2008,no. 5.

——. “The Distance between Ideal and Reality” (理想与现实的距离). In Polemics over the Drafting of a Civil Code for China (中国民法典起草思路论战), ed. Xu Guodong. Beijing: China University of

民法总则明确规定18周岁以上的人是否有民事能力-

民法总则明确规定18周岁以上的人 是否有民事能力? 相对之前的法律规定,民法总则有不少亮点,其中规定8周岁是限制民事行为年龄的分界点,而之前规定的是10岁。在传统观点上,年满18周岁就是成年人了,要对自己的行为负责。在这一点上,民法总则也有条文规定。那么,民法总则明确规定18周岁以上的人是否有民事能力?下面我们跟随小编了解下有关知识。 抵押贷款房屋抵押个人住房抵押贷款汽车抵押抵押合同二手房抵押贷款 相对之前的法律规定,民法总则有不少亮点,其中规定8周岁是限制民事行为年龄的分界点,而之前规定的是10岁。在传统观点上,年满18周岁就是成年人了,要对自己的行为负责。在这一点上,民法总则也有条文规定。那么,民法总则明确规定18周岁以上的人是否有民事能力?下面我们跟随小编了解下有关知识。

一、民法总则明确规定18周岁以上的人是否有民事能力? 民法总则第十七条至第二十五条对自然人的民事行为能力有详细规定。十八周岁以上的自然人为成年人。不满十八周岁的自然人为未成年人。成年人为完全民事行为能力人,可以独立实施民事法律行为。十六周岁以上的未成年人,以自己的劳动收入为主要生活来源的,视为完全民事行为能力人。 八周岁以上的未成年人为限制民事行为能力人,实施民事法律行为由其法定代理人代理或者经其法定代理人同意、追认,但是可以独立实施纯获利益的民事法律行为或者与其年龄、智力相适应的民事法律行为。 二、具备完全行为能力的条件是什么? 我国公民具有完全民事行为能力应当满足下列两个条件: 1、18周岁以上。我国《民法总则》规定,18周岁是我国自然人成年的界限。对于16周岁以上而不满18周岁,但是以自己的劳动收入为主要生活来源的自然人,法律将之视为完全民事行为能力人。最高人民法院《意见》第2条还对“以自己的劳动收入作为主要生活来源”的认定作出了具体的规定:“十六周岁不满十八周岁的公民,能够以自己的劳动取得收入,并能维持当地群众一般生活水平的,可以认定为以自己的劳动收入为主要生活来源的完全民事行为能力人。”

民法的理念

苏格拉底在与他人的辩论过程中,不是着眼于答案,而是引导对方去思考什么是勇敢、美德等“自身”。在他看来,人的智慧是灵魂的一种洞察能力或明智审慎能力,在于人不断地认识自己,有自知之明,从而行为适度。苏格拉底不仅解构了以往的哲学,也导引了新的哲学方向,使哲人思考问题的视角从自然界的现象转向了人自身,寻求人的理性能力的最高表达。正是以此为基础,柏拉图提出了“理念”概念,并以之为核心构建了他的理念论哲学体系。“理念”一词的希腊文是ε'τδοζ(复数是ε'τδη)和'τδ'εα,都出自动词“'τδε'τν”(意思是“看”),这两个词的原义是指呈现在视觉中的事物的形状,后来就从中引申出较抽象的“本性”、“种”等含义。在西方哲学史上,柏拉图最早把它变成了一个专门的哲学术语,并以其为核心概念建立了他的理念论哲学体系。 在柏拉图那里,理念具有多种不同的含义,它既是对事物的性质起决定作用的内在形式,又是逻辑上所讲的种概念,还是创造一件物品所根据的原型、本原和原因,具有本体论、目的论、认识论和发生学等多方面的含义,内含了人类理性的认知、建构和价值三大功能。从本体论上讲,理念是本体,是脱离和先于可感个体事物的客观实在;从目的论上讲,理念是万物追求的目标和赖以产生的动因;从认识论、逻辑学上讲,理念是种、一般概念、共相、范畴;从发生学上讲,理念是万物的本原、模型,可感个体事物是以同名的理念为模型,模仿或分有理念而派生出来的摹本。 理念论提出,理念才是真正的实在,现象世界的“美”、“勇敢”等都是模仿或分有了同名理念而得来。柏拉图把关于理念世界的认识称为知识,将关于现象世界的认识称为意见,“善”的理念是最高智慧。这样,在柏拉图那里,人们充其量只能得到对理念的认识,即知识。二重世界的划分使柏拉图的哲学具有神秘主义的特征,也使柏拉图哲学成为中世纪基督教神学产生的思想渊源。亚里士多德尽管对柏拉图哲学进行了激烈的批判,却并未摆脱这一思维范式,正是他最终确立了西方古典哲学的本体论思维方式,确立了主客二元模式的主导地位。及至把柏拉图的“神”换成必然性、理性,就是近代的理性主义。黑格尔哲学是理性主义的顶峰,也预示了这一思维方式的终结。正是因此,现代西方哲学的各派都把两千多年的西方哲学史视为柏拉图、亚里士多德哲学的延续与发展,是有其道理的。 “理念”概念的产生过程表现了人的自我意识提高的过程,是人对自身的主体能力返身自认的过程,这说明哲学从本性来说,“就是人以世界为中介的自我意识、自我理解、自我发展、自我创造、自我实现的一种理论活动、理论表达”。当然,柏拉图的“理念”概念存在着历史的局限性,他把原本属于人类自身特征之一的理性夸大为现实世界之外的、独立于人的另类存在,把世界二重化为理念世界与现象世界,没有看到人类理性的能动性,从而到遥远的天际去寻找“造物主”。 简析经济法理念的概念和特征(曹胜亮, 段葳) 摘要: 经济法理念是经济法适用的最高原理, 是对经济法应然规定性的理性的基本的认识和追求。对我国现有经济法理念的概念和特征作进一步的解析和整合, 在新形势下具有十分重要的意义。 一、理念的含义

第一章 民法学基础

第一章民法学基础

第一章民法学基础 第一节民法的概念 1、概念:调整平等主体的自然人、法人、其他组织之间的财产关系和人身关系的法律规范的总称。 2、民法的词源 古罗马法中的jus civile(市民法)和jus gentium(万民法) 法国民法典driot civil(市民法)日本学者翻译为“民法” 清末《大清民律草案》1929《中华民国民法典》 3、民法的含义 1)法律部门 2)民法典 3)民事法律规范 4)民法学 第二节民法的起源 大陆法系的渊源——罗马法编纂 罗马城邦国家间的贸易往来使商品生产高度发达,和一批优秀的法学家的存在,导致罗

马法成为“简单商品生产即资本主义前的商品生产的完善的立法”。 6世纪罗马帝国的法典编纂《罗马法大全》(又称《国法大全》、《民法大全》,包括《查士丁尼法典》、《学说汇纂》、《法学阶梯》、《新律》) 罗马私法的体系 资本主义民法的产生 中世纪封建制度对个人权利的漠视导致私法的倒退 近代资本主义民法的产生背景 1、封建制的崩溃和资产阶级的兴起,要求人身独立、保护私有财产、经济自由 2、国家和市民社会的分离私法自治

有代表性的资本主义民法典 1)法国民法典(1804)所有权绝对、契约自由、过失责任三大原则 2)德国民法典(1896)创立“五编制” 3)日本民法典(1898)拿来主义 4)瑞士民法典(1907)民商合一 大陆法系和普通法系 大陆法系起源于罗马法,以民法典为中心(民法法系),制定法为法的主要渊源。德国民法典的极端理性化与瑞士民法典的概括抽象化。大陆法国家判例的作用 ?普通法系(英美法系)以判例法为核心,不 存在民法典。民法由财产法、合同法、侵权 行为法等构成。普通法国家的制定法的作用我国民法的产生发展 1922年苏俄民法典(总则、物权、债、继承)中国的民事立法史 1、古代民刑不分。商品经济不发达、中央集权、以礼代法 2、近代民事立法:1911年《大清民律草案》、1929年《中华民国民法》 3、解放区和建国初期民事立法:婚姻法、土地

民法总则试题库(含答案及解析)

《中华人民共和国民法总则》题库 单选题 1、(单选题)根据《民法总则》的规定,法人解散的,除合并或者分立的情形外,()应当及时组成清算组进行清算。 A.清算义务人 B.利害关系人 C.主管单位 D.登记机关 正确答案:A 2、(单选题)《民法总则》规定,监护人应当按照()的原则履行监护职责。 A.遵守法律法规 B.尊重被监护人意愿 C.权利义务对等 D.最有利于被监护人 正确答案:D 3、(单选题)《民法总则》明确规定,十八周岁以上的自然人为成年人。成年人为完全民事行为能力人,可以()。 A.独立实施民事行为 B.独立实施民事法律行为 C.独立进行民事活动

D.独立承担民事责任 正确答案:B 4、(单选题)《民法总则》明确规定,民事主体的()受法律保护,任何组织或者个人不得侵犯。 A.财产和人身关系权利 B.人身权利、财产权利以及其他合法权益 C.被宪法赋予的权利 D.民事行为能力和民事责任能力 正确答案:B 5、(单选题)根据《民法总则》规定,自然人下落不明满()的,利害关系人可以向人民法院申请宣告该自然人为失踪人。 A.五年 B.二年 C.三年 D.四年 正确答案:B 6、(单选题)根据《民法总则》的规定,()以上的未成年人为限制民事行为能力人,实施民事法律行为由其法定代理人代理或者经其法定代理人同意、追认,但是可以独立实施纯获利益的民事法律行为或者与其年龄、智力相适应的民事法律行为。 A.十周岁 B.八周岁

C.十四周岁 D.六周岁 正确答案:B 7、(单选题)《民法总则》规定,对监护人的确定有争议的,由被监护人住所地的()指定监护人。 A.居民委员会、村民委员会或者民政部门 B.民政部门 C.居民委员会、村民委员会 D.民政部门和公益组织 正确答案:A 8、(单选题)《民法总则》规定,不能辨认或者不能完全辨认自己行为的成年人,(),可以向人民法院申请认定该成年人为无民事行为能力人或者限制民事行为能力人。 A.其近亲属或者有关组织 B.其法定监护人或者有关组织 C.其法定代理人或者有关组织 D.其利害关系人或者有关组织 正确答案:D 9、(单选题)《民法总则》明确规定,法人是具有民事权利能力和(),依法独立享有民事权利和承担民事义务的组织。 A.民事行为能力 B.人格尊严

2017年最新民法总则解读

2017年最新民法总则解读

2017年最新民法总则解读 2017年最新民法总则于2017年3月15日通过发布,自2017年10月1日起实施。这次民法总则全文的出台,暂不废止民法通则,民法总则与民法通则的规定不一致的,根据新法优于旧法的原则,适用民法总则的规定。现对民法总则的八大亮点进行整理,希望对大家有帮助。 1、彩礼退不退,终于有说法 《民法总则》第8条:民事主体从事民事活动,不得违反法律,不得违背公序良俗。 解读: 其中最典型的就是彩礼钱,虽然法律中对于“彩礼钱”这部分财产并没有直接的规定,但是依据民法总则的规定,没有法律规定时,可以适用当地的习惯,但是有一个限制性条件,就是不可以违背国家社会存在和发展的公共秩序和善良风俗。这就是说,如果当地有“离婚退彩礼”的习惯,那么法律上也会给予支持。 2、胎儿也有继承权 《民法总则》第16条:涉及遗产继承、接受赠与等胎儿利益保护的,胎儿视为具有民事权利能力。但是胎儿娩出时为死体

监护职责部分或者全部委托给他人,导致被监护人处于危困状态的; (三)实施严重侵害被监护人合法权益的其他行为的。 本条规定的有关个人和组织包括:其他依法具有监护资格的人,居民委员会、村民委员会、学校、医疗机构、妇女联合会、残疾人联合会、未成年人保护组织、依法设立的老年人组织、民政部门等。 前款规定的个人和民政部门以外的组织未及时向人民法院申请撤销监护人资格的,民政部门应当向人民法院申请。 解读: 近年来,虐待孩子的事件屡见不鲜,这次民法总则规定,出现上述法条规定的情形,由法院指定新的“父母”。同时也可以给不合格的“父母”改正的机会,如果原来的父母被“解雇”后,确有悔改情形的,经其申请,法院可视情况恢复。但是“悔改权”仅限孩子的亲生父母,且是否能恢复,还要看孩子的父母是否确有悔改以及孩子是否接受。 5、个人信息泄露有了保障 《民法总则》第111条:自然人的个人信息受法律保护。任何组织和个人需要获取他人个人信息的,应当依法取得并确保信息安全,不得非法收集、使用、加工、传输他人个人信息,不得非法买卖、提供或者公开他人个人信息。

民法典的当代意义

民法典的当代意义 2020年5月28日,第十三届全国人民代表大会第三次会议表决通过了民法典,开启了我国法治的新时代。我国民法典采用了两步走的编纂战略,而2017年通过的民法总则是其中关键的一步。民法典“总则编”基本保持了民法总则的内容,同时又有所变动,例如,将民法总则中一个月、三个月等短期期间改为以日计算。总结新冠肺炎疫情应对经验,要求紧急情况下居民委员会、村民委员会或者民政部门须为被监护人安排必要的临时生活照料设施。不对法人和非法人组织的人格权设兜底性规定,只限定列举名称权、名誉权、荣誉权。此外,还修改了部分词句,调整了部分标点,表述更为精准。 “总则编”覆盖民法各编,形成了总分结合、动静结合的法典结构。在静态上规定了自然人、法人、非法人组织三类主体,民事权利、民事责任等民事法律关系的内容,在动态上规定了民事法律行为、代理、诉讼时效等法律关系变动原因。 “总则编”实现了制度传承与学说借鉴的结合。一方面,传承了民法典之前的立法经验,坚持权利本位和社会本位的结合,采取了民商合一的立法模式,并行规定了停止侵害式责任与损害赔偿责任。另一方面,借鉴相关学说新增绿色原则、决议行为,重新定义了民事法律行为,删除了民事制裁制度等。 “总则编”奠定了私法基本精神,契合了社会现实需求。其明确规定平等、自愿、公平、诚信、守法与公序良俗、绿色六大原则,科学设计民事法律行为与代理,专章规定民事权利,宣示财产权利平等保护、

厘定征收征用的条件和补偿,集中体现了私法自治的理念或精神。“总则编”积极回应社会关切,贯彻落实社会主义核心价值观。为适应和解决当前社会严重的人口老龄化、留守儿童问题,规定了成年监护、撤销监护;适应建设创新型国家的需求,建立了知识产权一般条款;积极应对信息网络时代的挑战,明确保护个人信息,宣示保护数据和网络虚拟财产。 比较此前的立法,“总则编”存在许多创新。 第一章“基本规定”按照潘德克顿式立法技术,形成了统领总则其他章节的一般内容。明确了立法目的、基本原则、法律渊源等法律解释适用的基本前提。确立绿色原则,以适应我国生态文明建设任务;“公序良俗”正式进入民法,并成为兜底性强制性规定,确立了私法自治的消极界限;明确了习惯的法源地位,扬弃了以往将国家政策作为法源的做法。 第二章“自然人”坚持民法的人文关怀,具体落实了主体平等、保护弱者等原则。调整了自然人出生和死亡时间的判断标准,降低了限制民事行为能力年龄门槛,强调胎儿利益的特殊保护。以“不能辨认”和“不能完全辨认”这种更为人性化的表述来替代以往“精神病人”的表述,增加了行为能力认定制度中的国家干预,允许有关组织进行无民事行为能力人或限制民事行为能力人的认定与恢复。丰富完善了监护制度,新增了遗嘱监护、成年监护等类型,以实现尊重被监护人的意愿、最有利于被监护人利益、实体和程序相结合、私法自治和国家强制相结合等原则。

民法学_王利明_绪论

第一节民法学 一、民法的定义 民法,是调整地位平等的民事主体之间在从事民事活动过程中发生的财产关系和人身关系的法律规范。民法是国家统一的法律体系中一个独立的法律部门,是重要的基本法。 “民法”一词源自古罗马的市民法(jus civile),反映着古代社会简单商品经济活动的根本要求。伴随着千百年人类文明发展的历程,民法逐渐形成调整不同社会形态下与商品经济相适应的平等主体之间发生的财产关系和人身关系的法律制度。 民法的基础特征是: 第一、民法在本质上反映了商品经济活动的客观要求。 第二、民法所调整的社会关系其主体之间的地位是平等的。 第三、民法所调整的社会关系在内容上表现为财产关系和人身关系。 第四、民法是调整平等主体之间的财产关系和人身关系的法律规范的总和。 二、民法学的基本内容 民法学,是研究民事法律制度、民事法律现象和民法所反映的社会发展规律的科学。民法学是法学体系中一个独立的学科,是培养人的法律意识的基本理论之一。 民法学是人类文明的成果,反映着人类探索民事法律制度产生、发展和变化的思想成就。虽然在不同历史时期和不同国家民法学的观点、体系有所差异,但其研究对象和研究内容却是一脉相承、不断深化着的。民法学的科学精神和丰富的知识体系,为正确制定民事立法、指导司法审判实践、提高人们的法制思想水平,推动社会经济发展和文明进步,具有重要的理论价值和实践意义。 民法学的基本内容是: 第一、民法总论。该部分从宏观的角度分析和研究民法的调整对象,民法的基本原则、民事法律关系、民事权利主体(公民与法人等)、民事权利客体、民事法律行为、代理和时效。 第二、物权。该部分主要研究物权法总论、财产所有权、共有、相邻关系、用益物权、担保物权和占有。 第三、债权。该部分主要研究债权总论、合同法基本原理、合同法分论、不当得利和无因管理。 第四、人身权。该部分主要研究具体的人格权和身份权制度、以及如何对人身权给予全面、有效的民法保护。 第五、知识产权。该部分除一般地研究知识产权原理外,主要是具体研究著作权、专利权和商标专用权制度。 第六、继承权。该部分主要研究继承法总论、法定继承、遗嘱继承和遗产的处理。 第七、民事责任。该部分主要研究民事责任的概念、民事责任的归责原则、违反合同的民事责任和侵权的民事责任。 三、民法学的学习方法 民法学在法律科学体系中属于部门法学和应用法学。因为这门法学是专以民事法律制度、民事法律现象和民法所反映的社会发展规律为研究对象的。它不仅要研究民事法律制度产生和发展的规律,更要探索民事法律制度的具体规则和法律适用的方法。所以,学习民法学,首先要坚持理论联系实际的科学方法。应当密切关注当代经济全球化的社会发展趋势对我国市场经济的深刻影响,把握我国经济体制改革对民事法律制度的客观要求,了解司法审判实践出现的新情况和新问题,从而使我们对民法学的学习置于活生生的社会生活之中,学习有针对性,收获有现实性。

民法总论第一章知识点整理

?第一章民法概述 【本章重点】:民法的概念、调整对象、特点、体系 【本章难点】:民法调整对象中财产关系和人身关系 【基本要求】 一、了解:民法的起源与发展 二、理解:民法的表现形式 三、掌握:民法的性质 ?第一节民法的调整对象 一、民法的含义 (一)民法的起源及发展过程 1、民法一词来源于罗马法中的市民法 2、我国古代没有民法,古代诸法合一,民刑不分 清朝末年清政府派沈家本修订法律,聘请日本的松冈义正起 草民法,1911年完成了一部《大清民律草案》 《大清民律草案》意义:是中国历史上第一个民法典草案,有民法的内容,但不能称为民法(重点颁布时间和意义) 3、南京国民政府成立之后,设立民法起草委员会,参考德、日、 前苏联的立法经验,在1929年5月23日颁布《中华民国民法》 《中华民国民法》意义:是我国历史上第一部正式的民法典 (重点颁布时间及意义) 4、1949年,中华人民共和国成立后,立法机关在1954年—1959年 (大跃进),1962年—1964年(文革前期)两次组织起草民法典, 但是因政治、经济、思想的原因搁浅了,1979年—1982年(改革 开放)听取邓小平的建议起草民法,不过由于讨论计划经济和市 场经济谁重要,由于政治原因,也没有立法成功。 5、1986年准民法典《中华人民共和国民法通则》正式出台,1987年1月1日正式实施,标志着我国新时期民法典步入了新的进程,为我国构建现代化民法体系奠定了基础。(重点同上) 6、2016年6月、10月、12月,全国人大常委会先后3次审议了民法总则草案,2017年3月15日第十二届全国人民代表大会第五次会议通过了2017年10月1日正式实施的《中华人民共和国民法总则》,意味着我国民法典编撰工作第一部已经完成,在我国民法史上具有里程碑的意义。 (重点同上) 需要同学们每人准备《中华人民共和国民法通则》和《中华人民共和国民法总则》 (二)民法的含义 1、概念 民法是调整平等主体的自然人、法人及其他组织之间的人身关 系和财产关系的法律规范的总称(需要理解为什么是总称) 总称的原因:由多个法律组成,各种规范的总称。如中华人民共和国民法总则 2、含义 (1)民法是一个独立的法律部门 (2)民法只调整人身关系和财产关系,不调整其他关系

民法总则试题库(含答案与解析)

WORD 格式可编辑 《中华人民共和国民法总则》题库 单选题 1、(单选题)根据《民法总则》的规定,法人解散的,除合并或者分立的情形外,()应当及时组成清算组进行清算。 A.清算义务人 B.利害关系人 C.主管单位 D.登记机关 正确答案: A 2、(单选题)《民法总则》规定,监护人应当按照()的原则履行监护职责。 A.遵守法律法规 B.尊重被监护人意愿 C.权利义务对等 D.最有利于被监护人 正确答案: D 3、(单选题)《民法总则》明确规定,十八周岁以上的自然人为成年人。成年人为完全 民事行为能力人,可以()。 A.独立实施民事行为 B.独立实施民事法律行为 C.独立进行民事活动 D.独立承担民事责任 正确答案: B 4、(单选题)《民法总则》明确规定,民事主体的()受法律保护,任何组织或者个 人不得侵犯。 A.财产和人身关系权利 B.人身权利、财产权利以及其他合法权益 C.被宪法赋予的权利 D.民事行为能力和民事责任能力 正确答案: B 5、(单选题)根据《民法总则》规定,自然人下落不明满()的,利害关系人可以向 人民法院申请宣告该自然人为失踪人。 A.五年 B.二年 C.三年 D.四年 正确答案: B 6、(单选题)根据《民法总则》的规定,()以上的未成年人为限制民事行为能力人, 实施民事法律行为由其法定代理人代理或者经其法定代理人同意、追认,但是可以独立实施 纯获利益的民事法律行为或者与其年龄、智力相适应的民事法律行为。 A. 十周岁 B. 八周岁

C.十四周岁 D.六周岁 正确答案: B 7、(单选题)《民法总则》规定,对监护人的确定有争议的,由被监护人住所地的() 指定监护人。 A.居民委员会、村民委员会或者民政部门 B.民政部门 C.居民委员会、村民委员会 D.民政部门和公益组织 正确答案: A 8、(单选题)《民法总则》规定,不能辨认或者不能完全辨认自己行为的成年人,(), 可以向人民法院申请认定该成年人为无民事行为能力人或者限制民事行为能力人。 A.其近亲属或者有关组织 B.其法定监护人或者有关组织 C.其法定代理人或者有关组织 D.其利害关系人或者有关组织 正确答案: D 9、(单选题)《民法总则》明确规定,法人是具有民事权利能力和(),依法独立享有 民事权利和承担民事义务的组织。 A.民事行为能力 B.人格尊严 C.民事法律能力 D.民事责任能力 正确答案: A 10、(单选题)《民法总则》规定,民事主体从事民事活动,不得违反法 律,不得违背()。 A.合法合理原则 B.公序良俗 C.社会主义核心价值观 D.相关行政法规 正确答案: B 11、(单选题)《民法总则》规定了()的民事权利能力一律平等。 A.自然人 B.民事主体 C.公民 D.公民与法人 正确答案: A 12、(单选题)《民法总则》规定,未成年人的父母已经死亡或者没有监护能力的,由下 列有监护能力的人按顺序担任监护人:(一)祖父母、外祖父母,(二)兄、姐,(三)其他 愿意担任监护人的(),但是须经未成年人住所地的居民委员会、村民委员会或者民政部门 同意。 A.法人或者单位 B.个人或者组织 C.单位或者组织

现代民法的人文精神.doc

现代民法的人文精神- 摘要:现代民法的人文精神是全面主体性与严格自由主义的统一。具体而言,现代民法的人文精神表现为对实质正义、个别正义的追求,对人格权的关注以及对所有权绝对、契约自由和过失责任等三大近代民法原则的修正与限制。现代民法的人文精神是对近代民法的人文精神的扬弃,是人类朝着纯粹的理想的人文精神前进的一个重要环节,它反映了我们这个时代的时代精神,是对近代民法人文精神中二律背反的克服,具有辩证法的色彩,必将极大推动人的解放和人的全面自由发展。 一.什么是民法的人文精神? 一部民法史,就是市民社会、民法、人文精神互动的关系史,一部弘扬民法的人文精神和推动人的自由全面发展的历史。在民法文明这一个历史形态中,人终于或多或少地发现了马克思所说的人的全面自由的发展及对人的本质的占有。虽然作为历史范畴的民法文明会因历史传统、经济制度、政治制度和地理环境等诸因素影响具有历史局限性,但是只要人文精神是它的精神和追求,那么它引导人民走提升主体性及高扬自由平等精神的本质就不会改变,否则它不成其为民法。因此作为历史范畴的民法所抽象的”民法人”,一方面具有历史局限性,他要反映并记录那个时代的时代精神,另一方面,他又具有历史进步性,他要弘扬和实现民法的人文精神,这是人类认识非至上性与至上性、真理的相对性与绝对性在民法文明中的矛盾表现。民法的崇高正在于它以人文精神唤醒人去做一个”民法人”,从而使他在人的解放的道路上前进。所以耶林说:”罗马帝国曾三次征服世界,第一次以武力,第二次以宗教,第三次以法律。武力因罗马帝国的灭亡而

消失,宗教随着人民思想觉悟的提高、科学的发展而缩小了影响,唯有法律征服世界是最为持久的征服。”罗马法律对世界的征服之所以最为持久,既在于其私法制度的相对完备,更在于其私法精神对人的权利的肯定、对人的关怀已蕴涵了近代、现代民法人文精神的胚胎。 我们认为,民法的人文精神是民法文明内在、深层的精髓与内核,是民法文明的价值追求和终极关怀,是民法的最高原则。一方面,它旨在高扬人的主体性,肯定人的尊严与价值,肯定人-物关系中人的主体地位,对这一关系作出民法回答;另一方面,它旨在弘扬自由的精髓,肯定有限制的自由主义的价值,肯定人-人关系中的自由与平等,对这一关系作出民法回答。简言之,民法的人文精神就是主体精神与自由精神。 我们可以说近代民法的人文精神是市民社会及哲学革命矛盾运动的产物。首先,近代民法肯定提升了人的主体性,在人类历史上第一次真正把所有人生而平等享有权利写进了法典,承认了人的独立性与平等性,使人从等级、身份制度的压迫中解放出来,它是以尊重人、肯定人、解放人为己任的;但另一方面,它对人的独立性与平等性的关怀又是形式上的,以物的依赖性为基础的,这导致了近代民法关注形式正义、整体正义而忽视实质正义、个别正义和重物轻人、重客体轻主体的现象,使民法降格为单纯的财产法。其次,近代民法以唯理主义和自由主义为其灵魂,奉”所有权绝对,契约自由和过失责任”为圭臬,与此同时它的革命性又把辩证法的另一面丢掉了,缺少应有的相对的一面和节制精神。所以说,近代民法的人文精神是矛盾的统一,它具有二律背反和形而上学的色彩。一言以蔽之,近代民法的人文精神是片面主体性与绝对自由主义,它反映了那个时代的时代精神。近代

民法总则明确规定法人应当具备哪些条件

民法总则明确规定法人应当具备哪 些条件 民法总则明确规定法人应当具备的条件有既定的民事组织具有一定的经济能力的团体,法人不是常识中的个体,有关的当事人需要清楚详细的解释,尽量避免不必要的纷争,同样我们也应该清楚法人不仅意味着权益也有责任,有关的当事人需要多加注意。 一,民法总则明确规定法人应当具备哪些条件 法人是具有民事权利能力和民事行为能力,依法独立享有民事权利和承担民事义务的组织.这种组织既可以是人的结合团体,也可以是依特殊目的所组织的财产.从根本上讲,法人与其他组织一样,是自然人实现自身特定目标的手段,它们是法律技术的产物,它的存在从根本上减轻了自然人在社会交往中的负担。. 法人应当依法成立.法人应当有自己的名称、组织机构、住所、财产或者经费.法人成立的具体条件和程序,依照法律、行政

法规的规定.设立法人,法律、行政法规规定须经有关机关批准的,依照其规定。 二、法人的民事责任由谁承担? 1、法人以其全部财产独立承担民事责任。 2、依照法律或者法人章程的规定,代表法人从事民事活动的负责人,为法人的法定代表人.法定代表人以法人名义从事的民事活动,其法律后果由法人承受.法人章程或者法人权力机构对法定代表人代表权的限制,不得对抗善意相对人。 3、法定代表人因执行职务造成他人损害的,由法人承担民事责任.法人承担民事责任后,依照法律或者法人章程的规定,可以 向有过错的法定代表人追偿。 三、法人解散的原因有哪些? 1、有下列原因之一并依法完成清算、注销登记的,法人终止。 (1)法人解散。 (2)法人被宣告破产。 (3)法律规定的其他原因。 法人终止,法律、行政法规规定须经有关机关批准的,依照其规定。

民法与弱者保护

民法与弱者保护 本文从网络收集而来,上传到平台为了帮到更多的人,如果您需要使用本文档,请点击下载按钮下载本文档(有偿下载),另外祝您生活愉快,工作顺利,万事如意! 现代社会赋予传统意义上的“弱者”多重身份,这样的多层次性使得民法在保护弱者的同时,与现实情况不断产生博弈,由此带来的效果在形式公平与实质公平之间摇摆。法律的保护应当基于有效性以及针对性,以特定目的的达到来维护公平和更好的社会秩序。 无论是从人文关怀的角度出发,亦或是基于现代社会的经济发展现状而进行考究,法律体系的不断发展无一不是为了实现对“弱者”的利益进行实质上的保护并不断加强这一最基本而又迫切的目的。而民法的最根本原则,是为在法律面前,保护不同的主体之间各方面权利义务的平等关系,实现公平正义原则,均衡强弱方的彼此利益。在对需要法律保护意义上的“弱者”进行定义、对保护的过程进行完备、对不够及时和到位的保护手段进行有效修缮,已经渐渐演变成为社会性关注的焦点之一。 一、“弱者”的定义

首先,从法律关系上看,并没有自诞生便被定义为“弱者”身份的法律主体。 一切的“强与弱”关系的比较,都是源自于在“某一段特定的法律关系、社会关系当中,情形处于劣势的一方”可称为相对意义上的弱者。亦即,“弱者”,是经由两个及其以上的主体,通过在某方面的相似属性进行对比参照后得出的暂时性身份。这样对比之后所得到的结果,意味着居于弱势情形的一方的地位并非是长期固定不产生变化的。并且,在不同的法律关系和社会关系的前提下,“强与弱”的身份地位可出现一定的转换,并不具有固定不变的性质。通过多方不同的参考基线的比较,我们通常会从主体的主客观大致方面来判断一方是否处于弱势地位。大体上讲,主要是从三方面来进行判别:身体与精神的健康状况、智力水平的高低、个体所拥有财富的数量。而民法作为调整有关“市民”一切法律关系的规范准则,其法律价值自始至终贯穿于以上三个方面,再到最后以一定的经济关系与社会效应得到展现。民法对弱者的保护所体现的方面与刑法在有关方面的惩罚性作用上是不同的,它更注重于当“弱者”的各项合法权益遭受到侵害的事实发生以后,如何及时、有效地采取合理的手段

第一编 民法总论习题(含答案)

《民法练习题集》 第一章民法概述 名词解释题: 1民法 选择题 (一)单项选择题 下列哪一个选项属于“私法”范畴?()(考研) A行政法B组织法 C婚姻家庭法D刑法,程序法 (二)多项选择题 查士丁尼《民法大全》在罗马法典编纂方面最富成效和影响力,该《民法大全》由哪几部分组成?() A查士丁尼法典B学说汇纂 C法学阶梯D查士丁尼新律 关于形式意义上的民法和实质意义上的民法,下列说法正确的是()。

A从法律发展史上看,先有实质意义上的民法,后有形式意义上的民法 B现代社会,各国既有实质意义上的民法,又有形式意义上的民法 C形式意义上的民法能涵盖民事生活全部,有形式意义上的民法就不需要实质意义的民法 D实质意义上的民法不能否认形式意义上的民法,后者可以对前者归纳整理并予以体系化 对于民法调整的人身关系和财产关系,下列说法不正确的是()。 A人身关系都具有固有性 B等价有偿原则不适用于人身关系 C侵害人身利益的情形下刑罚保护手段更严厉,所以可以代替民法保护手段 D人身关系具有非财产性,所以与财产关系没有联系 下列选项中不可以作为我国民法渊源的是()。 A习惯 B最高人民法院关于适用《中华人民共和国合同法》若干问题的解释(一) C某学者关于名誉权保护的专著 D最高人民法院的生效判决

简答题 简述民法调整人身关系的必要性和特点。(考研) 参考答案 名词解释题: 人身关系,是指没有财产内容但有人身属性的社会关系。人身关系是基于一定的人格和身份产生的,体现的是人们精神上和道德上的利益,包括人格关系和身份关系两类。 选择题 (一)单项选择题 答案:C 本题考查公私法的划分。私法主体能够自由作出决策,不同于刑法、行政法、组织法等公法部门,我国婚姻家庭法从民法中分离出去,成为相对独立的法律部门,但是仍然属于私法的范畴,是私法多元体制下的重要部分。

民法总论笔记 (1)

绪论 一、马克思主义是民法学研究的理论基石 民法学应以马克思主义为指导,具体表现在如下几个方面: (1 (2 (3(4 二、从民法的历史发展认识民法 (一)民法主要起源于罗马法——罗马奴隶制国家施行的法律 (二)从近代民法到现代民法 1. 近代民法——经过十七八世纪的发展,于19世纪经欧洲各 国编纂民法典而逐步形成的一整套民法概念、 原则、制度、理论和思想的体系,在范围上包 括德国、 法国、瑞士等大陆法系国家民法。 主要特点:(1)抽象的人格平等; (2)无限制私有权原则; (3)契约自由; (4)过失责任原则。 2. 现代民法——近代民法在20世纪的发展与修正 主要特征:(1)对所有权的限制; (2)对合同自由的限制; (3)归责原则的多元化; (4)人格权制度的勃兴; (5)侵权法的独立与扩张; (6)交易规则的国际化趋势; (7)注重对弱势群体的保护。 (三)我国民法的发展及未来 (四)从民法的基本特征认识民法——民法的性质 ▲ 1. 民法是私法(公法的对称) 2. 民法是市场经济的基本法 3. 民法是权利保障法 4. 民法是人法 三、构建中国特色的民法学理论体系 (一)中国特色民法学理论体系的含义 (二)中国特色民法学理论体系的特征 ▲ 1. 本土性 2. 实践性 3. 包容性 4. 时代性 5. 科学性 (三)未来我国民法学的发展 第一,民法价值的发展; 第二,民法内容的发展; 第三,民法体系的发展; 第四,民法与相关法律部门的衔接; 第五,民法方法的多样性; 第六,民法与其他学科之间的沟通与交流。 四、学习民法学的具体方法 一是准确掌握民法概念; 二是娴熟地运用类型化和体系化的研究方法; 三是重视运用逻辑的方法; 四是掌握法律解释的方法; ▲ 五是注重借鉴经济学、社会学、哲学、历史学、心理学甚至统计 学等其他社会科学的研究方法。

民法总则新规定

一、诉讼时效期间由两年延长为三年 重要性:★★★★★ 第一百八十八条向人民法院请求保护民事权利的诉讼时效期间为三年。法律另有规定的,依照其规定。 本条将普通诉讼时效的期间由两年延长为三年。有关期间的修改,在实务中最需要注意的是法律的溯及力问题。关于溯及力问题,最高人民法院有可能会制定专门的司法解释。在解释未公布前,可以作为参考的是1999年施行的《合同法》对此前《技术合同法》(已被《合同法》废止)中关于技术合同争议的诉讼时效作出延长时,最高人民法院在司法解释中所确立的溯及力原则。《技术合同法》规定,技术合同争议的诉讼时效期限为一年。而根据《合同法》的规定,技术合同争议的诉讼时效应适用普通诉讼时效期间,为两年。最高人民法院《关于适用〈中华人民共和国合同法〉若干问题的解释(一)》就此确立的原则是,技术合同争议当事人的权利受到侵害的事实发生在合同法实施之前,自当事人知道或者应当知道其权利受到侵害之日起至合同法施行之日超过一年的,人民法院不予保护;尚未超过一年的,其提起诉讼的时效期间为两年。参考该解释,本次《民法总则》将普通诉讼时效期间由两年延长为三年,有可能确立的溯及力规则为:当事人的权利受到侵害的事实发生在《民法总则》实施之前,自当事人知道或者应当知道其权利受到侵害之日起至《民法总则》施行之日超过两年的,人民法院不予保护;尚未超过两年的,其提起诉讼的时效期间为三年。 需要引起关注的是,虽然《民法总则》已经公布,但施行日期为今年的10月1日,在此之前,仍以两年标准为确定诉讼时效,切勿因此延误主张权利而导致诉讼时效经过。 二、重大误解撤销权行使期间缩短为三个月 重要性:★★★★★ 第一百五十二条有下列情形之一的,撤销权消灭:

民法的精神

对民法精神的思考 ——土木工程专业今天晚上我认真聆听了法学院教授的一节关于民法精神的课,对老师介绍的关于中国民法中的诚信原则感到受益匪浅,此外还感受到诚信原则与我们生活息息相关,不仅如此,在我所学的土木专业这一块将来与诚信原则也密不可分。 根据我上课所听的内容和课后在图书馆和网络上找到的一些相关知识,我对诚信原则有以下几点认识。 首先,诚信原则在我国长期以来只被理解为客观诚信,并被理解为仅仅是财产法上的制度,忽略了诚信恶信问题与伦理学上的善恶问题的关联。即使在对相当于主观诚信的“善意”的研究中,也忽略了此等善意的个别性和地域性,由此忽略了主观诚信制度的保护弱者功能。 再者,我们来看看主观诚信和客观诚信,他们都具有保护弱者的功能。就主观诚信而言,其构成至少包括不知和错误两种形态,知并避免错误问题,在某种程度上是一个人在具体情境中的认知能力问题。认知能力的主体按自然身份可分为成年男子和妇女儿童,按生活环境可分为城市人和乡下人。在传统社会里,成年男子的认知能力高于妇女儿童,因为前者出门谋生,见多识广,还通常受一定教育,所以能读解或听闻法律的规定或其他生活事实。而妇女通常理家,文盲的比例大大高于男子;低龄的儿童不识字或识字不多,所以,即使法律有规定,他们也不能认知。因此,如果对法的不知构成诚信,他们在这方面的机会要多得多。在传统的社会里,城市人由于人际接触多而见多识广,乡下人由于人际接触少而孤陋寡闻,所以,后者发生认识错误的概率要大于前者。妇女儿童、乡下人由于一时的疏忽发生了不知或错误,法律仍对他们予以优待,这是对弱者的保护和照顾。 就客观诚信而言,它意味着行为人不利用对手的不知或疏忽牟利,而是公正行事,给予每个人属于他的,采取自己活,让人活的立场。这样行事的结果也保护了弱者。这样的功能体现在消费者保护上,即禁止欺压性条款上,法律裁定此等条款因为违反了诚信原则无效。由此看来,无论是主观诚信还是客观诚信,都是行其所言谓之信。 在社会层面上,人们为了保护自己的财产通过社会契约结合为社会,为此要承担彼此承认他人之所有权的义务。在物权法方面,明知财产为他人所有而仍占有之,就最大地违背了诚信,构成恶信,换言之,行为人违背了自己对其他社会成员所作的诺言。相反,若在不知或错误的情况下为此等占有,仍不失为诚信;在合同法方面,诚信地履行合同义务即为对其

参考教材民法王利明主编中国人民大学出版社民法教案

参考教材:民法(王利明主编中国人民大学出版社) 民法教案 王鑫 政法系 2015学年度第2学期 第一编民法总论 目录

第一章民法概述 第二章民法的基本原则 第三章民事法律关系 第四章自然人 第五章法人 第六章非法人组织 第七章民事权利 第八章物 第九章民事行为 第十章代理 第十一章期限与诉讼时效 参考资料一、主要参考法律法规 1.《中华人民共和国民法通则》

2.《最高人民法院关于贯彻执行<中华人民共和国民法通则>若干问题的意见(试行)》 3. 《中华人民共和国物权法》 4.《中华人民共和国合同法》 5.《中华人民共和国担保法》 6.《中华人民共和国继承法》 7.法国民法典 8.德国民法典 9.日本民法典 10.台湾民法典 10.苏俄民法典 二、参考文献 1.江平主编:《民法学》,中国政法大学出版社 2.刘凯湘:《民法学》,中国法制出版社 3.郭明瑞主编:《民法》,高等教育出版社 4.马俊驹/余延满:《民法原论》,法律出版社 5.高圣平/梅夏英:《物权法教程》,人民大学出版社 6.胡康生主编:《中华人民共和国物权法释义》,法律出版社

第一章民法概述 民法是法律体系中的一个独立的法律部门,居于基本法的地位。民法一词来源于罗马的市民法,罗马法奠定了现代民法的基础,而后1804年的法国民法典和1896年的德国民法典是现代大陆法系国家民法典的蓝本。 第一节民法的概念 一、民法的词源 民法一词来源于罗马法,罗马法在法律体系上也是诸法合一,但在学理上将法律分为公法和私法,古罗马法学家乌尔比安提出: “公法是关于罗马国家的法律(万民法),私法是关于个人利益的法律(市民法),即罗马法包括市民法和万民法,在查士丁尼制定《国法大全》时,两法已经合并,罗马法主要以私法为主。近代法国、德国、瑞士、日本等国的民事立法均为私法,从词源上看,民法是调整民间社会关系的法。 我国历史上最早的专门民事立法可追溯到1911年清政府的《大清民律草案》,(清政府委任沈家本等人为修订法律大臣,曾聘请日本学者松本义正等人起草该民法,民法学者一般认为中国“民法”一词源自日本,也有学者认为我国古代文献中便有“民法”一词,如《尚书.孔传》有文:“咎单,臣名,主土地之官,作《明居民法》一篇,亡。”)这是我国刑、民分立的第一个民法草案。但未及公布,清朝就覆亡了。民国成立后,北洋政府于1925年完成《中华民国民法草案》,但也未正式颁行。南京国民党政府以上述两草案为基础,借鉴法、德、瑞士、日本等国民法某些原则和条款,于1928年5月到1930年底制定民法典,分五编(总则编、债编、物权编、亲属编、继承编)陆续公布。它是我国历史上正式公布的第一部民法典,至今仍施行于台湾省。 二、民法的概念 民法是调整平等民事主体的自然人、法人、其他组织之间的财产关系和人身关系的法律规范的总称(《民法通则》第2条和《合同法》第2条)。“民法”一词有多种含义,应加以区别: (一)形式上的民法和实质上的民法 形式上的民法,专指系统编纂的民事立法,即民法典。实质上的民法指调整民事活动的所有法律规范的总称,它不仅包括形式上的民法或民法典,也包括单行的民事法规和其他法规中的民事法律规范。我国无民法典,但实质上的民法是存在的。 (二)广义的民法和狭义的民法 广义的民法是指调整民事活动的所有法律规范的总称,它不仅包括形式上的民法或民法典,也包括单行的民事法规和其他法规中的民事法律规范。市民法 1911年《大清民律草案》 1925年《中华民国民法草案》 1929.5.23公布《民法》总则

第一编+民法总论习题(含答案).

第一章民法概述 名词解释题: 1民法 选择题 (一单项选择题 下列哪一个选项属于“私法”范畴?((考研 A行政法B组织法 C婚姻家庭法D刑法,程序法 (二多项选择题 查士丁尼《民法大全》在罗马法典编纂方面最富成效和影响力,该《民法大全》由哪几部分组成?( A查士丁尼法典B学说汇纂 C法学阶梯D查士丁尼新律 关于形式意义上的民法和实质意义上的民法,下列说法正确的是(。A从法律发展史上看,先有实质意义上的民法,后有形式意义上的民法 B现代社会,各国既有实质意义上的民法,又有形式意义上的民法 C形式意义上的民法能涵盖民事生活全部,有形式意义上的民法就不需要实质意义的民法 D实质意义上的民法不能否认形式意义上的民法,后者可以对前者归纳整理并予以体系化 对于民法调整的人身关系和财产关系,下列说法不正确的是(。

A人身关系都具有固有性 B等价有偿原则不适用于人身关系 C侵害人身利益的情形下刑罚保护手段更严厉,所以可以代替民法保护手段 D人身关系具有非财产性,所以与财产关系没有联系 下列选项中不可以作为我国民法渊源的是(。 A习惯 B最高人民法院关于适用《中华人民共和国合同法》若干问题的解释(一 C某学者关于名誉权保护的专著 D最高人民法院的生效判决 简答题 简述民法调整人身关系的必要性和特点。(考研 参考答案 名词解释题: 人身关系,是指没有财产内容但有人身属性的社会关系。人身关系是基于一定的人格和身份产生的,体现的是人们精神上和道德上的利益,包括人格关系和身份关系两类。 选择题 (一单项选择题 答案:C 本题考查公私法的划分。私法主体能够自由作出决策,不同于刑法、

相关文档
最新文档